Main menu
The Binding Force of International Law
by Patrick M. Capps
I. Introduction
It is commonly understood that international law is, at least in part, a set of binding legal norms that regulate the relations between states. Inquiry into the notion of the binding force of international law is an examination of the reasons why states are commanded, permitted or prohibited from undertaking certain actions and how states acquire certain rights, duties, powers or immunities against other states. A starting point for considering the binding force of international law is the famous decision of the Permanent Court of International Justice on the 7 September 1927 which concerned a dispute between France and Turkey over a collision between the French steamer, the Lotus, and a Turkish collier. In its judgment, the Court set out that the binding force of international law arose from the actual or tacit consent of states. Consent, in other words, is a law-
The position in the Lotus Case is both widely accepted and highly controversial. In 1928 Brierly said that this decision was ‘based on the highly contentious metaphysical proposition of the extreme positivist school that the law emanates from the free will of sovereign independent States.’ (BRIERLY, 1928: 155) Elsewhere he explains why he thinks it is contentious. He says ‘consent cannot of itself create an obligation; it can do so only within a system of law which declares that consent duly given, as in a treaty or a contract, shall be binding on the party consenting.’ (BRIERLY, 1950: 54) Therefore, there is a theoretical hole in this positivist concept of obligation despite its simplicity, popularity and intuitive plausibility. It cannot explain why international law is binding as law.
An explanation must be found to show how Brierly’s ‘system of law’, whereby state consent becomes a law creating fact, arises. It is this explanation, rather than the superstructure of agreements and customs which form substantive international law, which forms the basis of a world public order. There are at least two types of answer to this problem. One denies that these fundamental norms exist at the heart of an autonomous legal order and, for this reason, international legal obligations do not exist. Norms which regulate inter-
II. Deniers of the Binding Force of International Law
The first argument rests upon the premise or argument that sovereign states are the highest source of legal authority. If such states were subject to international legal obligations which, for example, regulated the jurisdictional scope of their laws it would mean that they were not the highest source of legal authority and hence could not, by definition, be sovereign. This, then, sets up the choice between a world of sovereign states, or a global state governed by international law. There is no third alternative and the global state is theoretically, normatively or practically unacceptable. Therefore, international law and international legal obligation cannot, genuinely, exist.
A. Thomas Hobbes (1588-
One version of this argument is offered by the English philosopher Thomas Hobbes. Hobbes argued that legal obligations can only arise from the will of a sovereign legislator. Human beings agree to this way of governing their lives primarily because of the unreasonableness of the state of chaos and disorder which exists without the sovereign. He then argues that this logic does not imply a universal state to regulate a prima facie similar situation in international relations. One reason for this is that sovereign states do not have the same vulnerabilities as human beings (in that they don’t sleep or grow frail with age) and another is that an inter-
Hobbes does not think that international relations is completely devoid of rule-
B. John Austin (1790-
Albeit on the basis of an analytical or empirical rather than normative methodology, John Austin offers a similar argument to that of Hobbes. Austin claims that the sovereign as the source and enforcer of law is an essential component of legal order. While it is the case that the sovereign is present in all stable domestic legal orders, it is absent from international law. For this reason, he thinks that international law is better conceptualised as positive morality. International laws, therefore, are better understood as a set of posited rules but which do not carry genuine legal obligations.
C. Georg Jellinek (1851-
Another final example of this type of account of the binding force of international law, which steers between normative and empirical methodologies, is provided by Georg Jellinek in his ‘two-
Firstly, the sociological or psychological, side to Jellinek’s theory takes into account ‘the structural constraints imposed on State will by the environment.’ (KOSKENNIEMI, 2002: 201) This is much the same as Hobbes’s explanation of why states tend to act in certain ways in international relations. Secondly, domestic public and administrative law in general is, in effect, an exercise in self-
On this account, international law is, at best, understood as external state law or as a set of structural constraints placed on states by the warp and weft of international relations. Hans Kelsen (1881-
III. Explanations of the Binding Force of International Law
The second approach to solving the problem identified by Brierly is to claim that states are constrained by an autonomous international legal order based upon a set of rational or conventional norms which afford legal validity to the system and render its norms legally binding.
A. Hugo Grotius (1583-
The second approach approximates to the approach taken by Hugo Grotius in his foundational work on international law entitled De jure belli et pacis (1625). He claims that there are certain laws which must be the case ‘if people have a basic right not to be harmed in their lives, bodies and possessions [and] … a right to have their agreements kept.’ (HARRISON, 2003: 145) He furthermore argued that these laws could be unilaterally enforced by individuals, but that it was ‘much more conductive to the peace of individuals’ (GROTIUS, 1925: 91) that they submitted their wills to a sovereign state to operate as the arbiter and enforcer of these natural rights. However, the international legal order, he argued, was a set of natural laws which regulated the use of force by, and agreements between, states. These formed a body of norms called international law which were rationally binding and which could be unilaterally enforced by states. This is, then, a decentralised view of international legal order as opposed to the centralised conception of law associated with the modern state.
B. Immanuel Kant (1724-
Immanuel Kant thought that such rational natural laws provided the logical impetus to a form of cosmopolitan international order. Kant’s views on what this might mean remains unclear. At some points, he comes close to the Grotian view of international law by arguing against a global state and for a horizontal and diffuse form of international legal order. At others, he seems to advocate a more substantial form of global governance. This comprises of three interlocking forms of juridical constitution which regulate different spheres of human activity. These are (i) nation states; (ii) public international law; (iii) ‘the constitution conforming to the law of world citizenship’ (KANT, 1957: 10-
The seminal Kantian constructivist, John Rawls (1921-
C. Herbert Hart (1907-
A legal positivist like Herbert Hart would consider that there is a different explanation for the development of the basic rules which validate Grotius’ horizontal system. For Hart the validity of a legal system is determined by a rule of recognition. Presumably, in an international legal order, this rule of recognition allows legal officials in various states to discern their international legal obligations from other sorts of obligation (for example, the rules of etiquette regulating diplomatic visits). Although Hart is sceptical as to whether a rule of recognition exists in the international legal order, if it does, it comes into being because it is practised by legal officials and it is binding for this reason.[1] So the Grotian idea that there are natural laws discerned from reason are replaced in Hart’s account by conventional rules which have developed over (perhaps) hundreds of years.
D. Hedley Bull (1933-
Modern Grotians like Hedley Bull explain the binding force of international law by combining a natural law and conventional account. Bull considers that there are certain norms which are accepted by states as being necessary for social life to occur in international relations. These are an ‘empirical equivalent’ of natural law (BULL, 1977: 6). These rules require the preservation of the international society of states, the maintenance of the independence of states as well as providing a limit on violence and the stabilisation of property rights. This seems similar to the Grotian account. However, Bull then argues that this has to ‘be set against the cultural and historical forces that had helped shape the consciousness of society at any particular time and moulded perceptions of common values and common purpose.’ (BULL, 1977: xi) Therefore, the reasons why obligations arise are rooted in reason, but over time common values develop which help to generate a thicker conception of those norms which are obligatory in international law.
IV. Theoretical Problems with the Consent-
Two connected points need to be made about these various accounts of the binding force of international law. The first is to notice that there is little disagreement on the substantive norms which constitute international law. Restrictions on the use of force, the independence of states and pacta sunt servanda are uncontroversial norms which guide action in international relations. The differences between the accounts just considered surround the reasons why these substantive norms are binding on states. Those who deny that international law can be legally binding would consider these rules to be good rules-
Kelsen’s very controversial response to this distinction is that it collapses; both approaches map equally well on the corpus of positive norms which are normally called international law. Legal scientists can disagree on the question of why international law is valid but the substantive content of international law remains the same from either perspective. He claims ‘[b]oth frames of reference are equally correct and equally warranted. It is impossible to choose between them on the basis of legal science.’ (KELSEN, 1998: 535) One might be sceptical about the conceptual validity of this claim. This is because the coincidence that Kelsen points out may turn on the contingent empirical fact that it is normally states, through their consent, which make international law. Also, Kelsen’s approach moves the question of the bindingness of international law beyond the purview of legal science. John Finnis may be right when he suggests that much of Kelsen’s approach rests upon ‘an overtly fictitious construction designed to suppress theoretical questions rather than to answer them.’ (FINNIS, 1973: 67)
Secondly, this inquiry into the binding nature of international law has been restricted to considerations of how state consent becomes a law-
The Grotian approach is an intermediary between this ‘all-
Bibliography
Brierly J., ‘The “Lotus” Case’ [1928] 174 Law Quarterly Review 154
**Brierly J., The Basis of Obligation in International Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1958)
Brierly J., The Law of Nations (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1950)
**Bull H., The Anarchical Society (Palgrave-
Finnis J., ‘Revolutions and the Continuity of Law’ in A. Simpson (ed), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1973)
**Grotius H., The Rights of War and Peace (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1925, first published in 1625, translated by F. Kelsey)
Harrison R., Hobbes, Locke and Confusion’s Masterpiece (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2003)
**Hart H., The Concept of Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1961)
**Hollis M. and Smith S., Explaining and Understanding International Relations (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1990)
Jennings R. and Watts A., Oppenheim’s International Law, 9th edition (Longman, London, 1996, first published in 1905)
**Kant I., Perpetual Peace, (MacMillan, New Jersey, 1957, first published in 1795, translated by L. Beck)
**Kelsen H., ‘Sovereignty’ in S. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson (eds), Normativity and Norms (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998)
Kelsen H., Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2002, originally published in 1934)
Koskenniemi M., The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-
Oppenheim L., “The Science of International Law: Its Task and Method” (1908) 2 American Journal of International Law 313
**Rawls J., The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1999)
Tuck R., The Rights of War and Peace (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999)
(** indicates recommended reading)
Related Entries
binding force of constitutional law, John Austin, Convention, Game theory in jurisprudence, Hugo Grotius, HLA Hart, Thomas Hobbes, concept of law, legal positivism, pure theory of law.
Footnotes
[1] In chapter 10 of The Concept of Law (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1961), Hart denies that a rule of recognition exists in the relations between states and therefore it can be questioned whether an international legal order exists. He does, however, claim that ‘in this analogy of content, no other social rules are so close to municipal law as those of international law.’ (at 237) We might, however, conclude that Hart misinterpreted the sophistication of the regulatory framework existing in the relations between states at least since the advent of the United Nations system, and probably even before this development. On this point see Hart’s discussion on 257 concerning Article 38(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice in relation to the sources of international law.