Main menu
C. John Rawls: The Original Position Argument
Previous section: B. John Rawls: His Two Principles and Their Application
This entry discusses Rawls’s original position argument for his two principles of justice. It first explains the original position argument as a heuristic device intended to model the relationships between several fundamental idea(l)s implicit in the most basic question citizens face in a liberal democracy: How ought we organize our polity? It then explains how the argument as a heuristic device highlights the superiority of Rawls’s two principles of justice to its main utilitarian rivals.
I. Fundamental Idea(l)s and the Original Position
How ought we as democratic citizens organize our polity? To answer this question, Rawls recast it in the more basic and manageable terms of the original position argument. In A Theory of Justice Rawls developed the original position argument by specifying the circumstances of justice, the role of principles of justice in governing the institutional production and distribution of social primary goods, various formal requirements of justice, principles of rational choice, and so on. In Political Liberalism he recast the original position argument as a heuristic the power of which derives from its incorporating three fundamental idea(l)s. These are the idea(l)s of fair social cooperation, persons as free and equal citizens, and the well-
Rawls does not consider the question of whether we ought to have a polity. He devotes his attention to the question of what kind of polity we ought to have. When we inquire, as democratic citizens, into the kind of polity we ought to have, Rawls holds, we implicitly assume that our polity is a system of social cooperation from one generation to the next. What we want to know is how it ought to be organized. Because we think of ourselves collectively as the free and equal co-
The idea of social cooperation for mutual advantage presupposes two further ideas. Both are necessary to give determinate content to the idea of mutual advantage. The first is the idea of a metric in terms of which citizens are made better or worse off. The second is the idea of a baseline or default condition against which any proposed institutional arrangement can be assessed to determine whether it mutually advantages all subject to it.
As citizens we cooperate politically for the sake of various goods we could not secure adequately for ourselves without cooperation. Rawls calls these social goods. There are many social goods reasonably sought by at least some citizens in modern democracies. But the idea of mutual advantage presupposes a (public and easily deployed) metric applicable to all citizens. And so Rawls identifies a small number of “primary” social goods. These are social goods the possession of which it would be reasonable to suppose to the advantage of any, and thus each and every, citizen. They are goods responsive to the higher order interests all citizens have in the development and exercise of their two fundamental moral powers or capacities (discussed immediately after the next paragraph). These basic or generic goods Rawls labels “primary goods.” They include basic rights and liberties, diverse opportunities (including education and training) for office and authority, wealth and income, the social or public bases of self-
Rawls identifies the baseline or benchmark against which mutual advantage is to be assessed as the level of primary goods each citizen would enjoy if all citizens over a complete life received, or could reasonably expect, an equal share of society’s total cooperative output of primary goods. A distribution of primary goods is mutually advantageous, then, if for all citizens it improves over this egalitarian benchmark the received or reasonably expected share of primary goods. Unequal distributions of primary goods may be mutually advantageous, then. An unequal distribution may make it possible to increase the total cooperative product available for distribution over what would be available under an equal distribution. So long as all share in that additional cooperative product, all are mutually advantaged relative to the egalitarian benchmark. Here Rawls’s idea is that income differences may enhance overall social productivity by encouraging (or at least removing disincentives for) individuals to develop and exercise their socially useful or valued talents. So long as all share in the increased social product realized under a system of unequal incomes, unequal incomes may leave everyone better off than they would be were the total social product shared out equally under a system of equal incomes.
This egalitarian benchmark or baseline reflects the moral self-
When citizens ask for principles of social cooperation they could each publicly accept and voluntarily honor, they are not asking how they ought to organize the production and distribution of primary goods as men and women, or Blacks and Whites, or workers and capitalists, or Christians and non-
One final point regarding Rawls’s recasting of the question “How ought we as democratic citizens organize our polity?”: Rawls assumes that when we ask this question we’re aiming at a “well-
The foregoing should suffice to suggest how Rawls’s original position argument models the assumptions and key ideas implicit in, and thereby recasts, the basic question democratic citizens face. Because we are, as free and equal democratic citizens, inquiring into fair terms for the cooperative production and distribution of primary goods in a well-
II. Making the Case for the Two Principles
Rawls first compared his two principles to utilitarianism. He argued that agents in the original position would prefer his two principles for at least two reasons. First, his two principles firmly secure the basic liberties essential to citizens’ fundamental interests as both rational and reasonable, whereas utilitarianism does not. Utilitarianism carries always some real possibility (of an unknowable or uncertain probability) of a morally catastrophic loss of liberty for citizens. The two principles guarantee a satisfactory social world, at least in terms of basic rights and liberties. This satisfactory social world is rationally to be preferred over the potentially unsatisfactory social world governed by utilitarian principles. Second, as a matter of moral psychology, citizens cannot reasonably be expected voluntarily and reliably to honor utilitarian demands that leave subject to ongoing reassessment the basic rights and liberties essential to their fundamental interests. A polity organized on utilitarian principles will suffer, then, from instability to some nontrivial degree. A polity organized on the principles of justice as fairness will avoid at least this instability. Agents in an original position will prefer, then, the latter. This first comparison demonstrated, for Rawls, that fair terms of cooperation must include a liberty principle, and thus a constitutionally entrenched system of basic liberty rights, immune to being overturned by utilitarian considerations.
Rawls next compared his two principles to what he called “restricted utilitarianism.” Restricted utilitarianism accepts the liberty principle and its priority, accepts fair equality of opportunity, and accepts a social minimum or safety-
Rawls did not think the two comparisons yielded similarly strong results. He felt the first comparison pointed more decisively toward justice as fairness than the second. Still, overall, he maintained that the two comparisons taken together show that justice as fairness constitutes a better answer to our fundamental question as democratic citizens than the most familiar and politically tempting versions of utilitarianism. It best expresses our implicit commitment to mutual recognition and reciprocity as free equals in social and political life.
Following section: D. John Rawls: Procedural Justice and Legitimacy