Main menu
Objectivity of Legal Science
by Jan-
I. INTRODUCTION
Science by definition is objective. It aims at true statements, or at true or adequate theories, about a particular subject. The issue of the objectivity of legal science accordingly is whether what is called "legal science" complies with standards of scientific objectivity, that is, whether it deserves its name. However, it is not clear what exactly should be understood by "legal science". Legal disciplines are legal doctrine but also e.g. legal philosophy, legal theory, legal sociology, and legal history. Without doubt legal sociology and analytical legal theory, aiming at purely empirical or analytical investigation, qualify as legal sciences. This also holds for legal history, although interpretative and ideological elements may raise some doubts. On the other hand, legal philosophy usually is not called a science, as its main subjects are normative issues of law, morality and justice, although philosophical theories claim to be objectively valid. When the issue of the objectivity of legal science is raised one usually refers to legal doctrine, that is the systematic analysis of the positive law of a particular legal system. Legal doctrine is at the centre of the various legal disciplines, but there are doubts whether it can be regarded as a science. The development and qualification of legal doctrine as a science is peculiar to the continental legal tradition, in contrast to the anglo-
II. DISCUSSION
The main issues of legal doctrine are the identification, interpretation and systematization of positive law, which might seem to be descriptive and analytical issues. However, the aim of legal doctrine to give guidance to legal practice goes beyond pure systematic analysis of the law. Moreover, the normative character of law, that is, its claim to provide a common system of norms binding on all its addressees, puts in doubt whether even the identification of law is possible in a purely descriptive manner. Another problem is the indeterminacy of law. It requires interpretation, and this again might require normative conceptions of what would be the best continuation of existing legal practice. Finally, one might doubt whether the construction of legal theories systematizing positive law can be normatively neutral. Hence, the objectivity of legal doctrine is put in doubt by its practical aspirations as well as by the normative character of law, the indeterminacy of law, and the gap between the law as a normative system and theories about the law.
1. IDENTIFICATION OF LAW
Scientific objectivity presupposes an object about which one can make true statements. As the subject matter of legal doctrine is the law, its objectivity depends on the objectivity of law. Only insofar as law is objective, it is a suitable object for legal doctrine as a science. However, as law is not a determinate object but stated in form of internal normative judgements on the basis justificatory procedures, it is not in all respects a suitable object of scientific investigation.
There are various options to preserve objectivity of legal science in face of the normative and value-
a) REDUCTIONISM
Reductionism is found in conceptions of legal realism, reducing law either to legal practice, as by American legal realism (HOLMES, GRAY, FRANK), or to mental attitudes, as suggested by Scandinavian legal realism (HÄGERSTRÖM, OLIVECRONA, the early A. ROSS). Both approaches are, however, not satisfactory because they cannot account for the normative character of law and its action-
KELSEN's "Pure Theory of Law" suggests a legal science which acknowledges at the same time the normative character of law and the restriction to cognitive themes. The normative character of law is based on the idea of a basic norm (Grundnorm) which must be presupposed when making legal statements. However, the structure and content of law is exclusively determined by empirical-
This point was made by H.L.A. HART holding that Kelsen's "Grundnorm" is redundant. Hart develops a descriptive-
Hence, one should dismiss the attempt to make legal doctrince objective by restricting the concept of law in a way that includes only descriptive-
b) NORMATIVISM
According to normative theories of law, legal doctrine must elaborate normative theories. The problem is whether normative theories can be scientific. The ordinary usage of the term "scientific" seems to exclude this. However, if science is essentially characterised as an enterprise to gain knowledge, and to develop theories which are objectively valid, then one may ask whether normative theories of law can be objectively valid, and do provide knowledge about the law. This is the problem of moral cognitivism, and of the rational justification of norms. Although claims of ethical skepticism and ethical relativism that there are no objectively valid norms at all, may be exaggerated, claims that a moral reality exists which allowed to make objectively valid statements although seems to be unwarranted. A rational justification of norms may be possible in some cases, but its scope is limited.
Consequently, it seems most plausible the assumption that legal doctrine does not have the character of a pure, objective science. This does not eliminate the task of elaborating most precisely which parts of legal doctrine can claim objective validity, and which present merely individual normative claims of its author. However, the practical dimension of legal doctrine requires to make normative claims where valid law cannot be established objectively. In contrast, legal doctrine can be objective only insofar as law can be shown to be objective.
2. OBJECTIVITY OF LEGAL INTERPRETATION
One line of legal interpretation take interpretive theories of law which integrate issues of semantic interpretation and the construction of normative theories, suggested in particular by DWORKIN. An alternative is to distinguish between the ascription of legal validity to norms and the semantic interpretation of established legal norms. For reasons of analytical clarity, the second option seems to be preferable.
The objectivity of legal interpretation is denied by linguistic theories which claim that there is no objective meaning. Such theories are hardly plausible, as successful communication obviously is in general possible. Therefore, something like an objective, intersubjectively determined meaning seems to exist, although there are cases where there is no commonly shared interpretation.
However, there are controversies about the correct conception of semantic meaning. A traditional view, that the meaning of concepts includes sense and reference (extension), that its sense includes criteria shared by competent speakers, and that the extension of a concept is determined by these criteria, is the object of critique because it cannot give an adequate explication of controversies about semantic meaning. In case of dispute, this conception had to conclude that no semantic meaning existed.
A competing conception tries to apply the semantics developed by Kripke and Putnam (causal semantics or K-
Hence, one can sustain the claim of the objectivity of semantic interpretation, at least in some cases. On the other hand, a theory of semantic meaning does not suffice for legal interpretation. Legal interpretation is part of the application of law, which aims at establishing definitive norms with regard to particular cases. Thus, it must be integrated in a normative theory of legal argumentation. The relation of semantic arguments to substantial normative arguments in legal argumentation needs clarification, not only in cases of semantic indeterminacy but also in cases where a clear linguistic meaning conflicts with normative legal arguments. The objectivity of legal interpretation depends ultimately on normative legal argumentation, and hence on the general theory of legal discourse (cf. ALEXY 1989). Semantic arguments may be regarded as relevant data within such a theory.
3. OBJECTIVITY OF LEGAL THEORY CONSTRUCTION
Legal doctrine includes not only semantic interpretation of legal concepts but also normative conceptions as interpretation of positive law, like for example the doctrine that basic rights interpreted as objective principles influence the entire legal system. The objectivity of such interpretations depends partly on the objective validity of normative theories. Another source of objectivity may be seen in the coherence of such conceptions with the legal system.
Coherence includes various respects. It may refer to a relation of fit with pretheoretical or external data, in particular legal norms and decisions. The relation of pretheoretical stage and theory is a feature of Dworkin's conception of law as integrity (DWORKIN 1986). Dworkin distinguishes pre-
Alternatively, coherence may be seen as an internal feature of theories, comprising criteria of consistency, comprehensiveness, and the mutual support of different parts of the theory. Coherence as an internal feature of theories may be seen as an indicator of the objective validity of a theory. However, the relation of such a theory to the law as its object is only indirect. Law is elaborated by justificatory procedures of normative character, not by descriptive theorizing. Coherence as a requirement on theory construction is independent from and, moreover, may conflict with the structure of normative reasoning. For example, justifying an exception of the basis of equity arguments in particular cases is less coherent than principled decision-
Accordingly, there is a gap between theoretical reasoning about law and normative argumentation within the law. Legal doctrine tries to give a systematic account of the legal system in form of legal statements. Among them are statements aiming at being directly applicable. This requires formulation in descriptive terms with more or less fixed meaning. But legal norms are constituted by the balancing of normative arguments, and the relevant criteria of this balancing are not defined in descriptive language but are the concrete weights of the respective arguments. Even if at some moment a legal doctrine exactly fits the legal situation, the next case may show that this is not the case. Insofar as law is constituted by the balancing of normative arguments the possibility and even necessity to introduce exceptions regarding particular cases is inherent to the law and constitutes a peculiar form of defeasibility of legal statements. Normative reasoning within the law and theoretical reasoning based on coherence are different affairs.
The coherence of balancing is a third form of coherence, which follows its own criteria. Balancing decisions are based on two factors, the relative weights of the competing normative arguments, and the degree to what the claims of these arguments are satisfied or non-
III. CONCLUSION
Legal doctrine can be objective in various respects, and should be so. The respects in which objectivity is possible are mainly determined by the structure of the establishing legal norms by means of balancing of normative arguments, intersubjective reflection, and authoritative decision-
Related Entries
Coherence, Descriptive legal theory, Dworkin, Interpretation of law, Kelsen, Legal Science, Legal Dogmatics, Methodology (legal), Weighing and balancing.
Bibliography
Alexy, R. (1989), A Theory of Legal Argumentation (Orig.: Theorie der juristischen Argumentation, 2ed., Frankfurt/M. 1991)
Dworkin, R. (1986), Law's Empire, London
Greenawalt, K. (1992), Law and Objectivity, New York/Oxford
Hage, J. (2001), Formalizing Legal Coherence, Proceedings of the 8th Inter na tional Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, ACM, New York, 22pp.
Hage, J./Peczenik, A. (2000), Legal Knowledge about What?, in: Ratio Juris 13, 326-
Kelsen, H. (1960), Reine Rechtslehre, 2.ed., Wien
Klatt, M. (2004), Theorie der Wortlautgrenze, Baden-
Moore, M. (2004), Objectivity in Ethics and Law, Ashgate/Dartmouth
Stavropoulos, N. (1996), Objectivity in Law, Oxford 1996