Main menu
Ratio Decidendi
by Roger Shiner
The Problem
The ratio decidendi of a case is the ground or reason the case is decided in the way that it is decided. Theratio decidendi is the aspect of a case that determines or is dispositive for the decision in the case. Although the above characterization is expressed in very general terms, such that it could cover any source for the legal materials deployed in judicial decision-
It is therefore crucially important, from the point of view of understanding theoretically common law reasoning from precedent, that we can identify what it is with respect to some decided case that is the ratio decidendi of the case.
Discussion
The first point to be made in this project is that the ratio decidendi (whatever it is) is to be distinguished from an obiter dictum. In the course of an official written opinion, a judge or a court will say many things. They will review the agreed facts; they will review applicable legislation; they will review existing decisions; they will review submissions by counsel or by intervenors; they will present patterns of reasoning; they will ultimately render a verdict. Whatever the ratio decidendi is, it will found among all this material. The ratio will typically not be found among the various reviews mentioned above, nor in the verdict itself. It will typically be found in the reasoning presented for the verdict. Even there, however, judges both make remarks that specifically relate to the case in point, and remarks which are of a more general character, about possible implications of the instant case, about the state of the law generally, and so forth. These remarks are known as obiter dicta, expressions of opinion by a judge that are external to the dispositive reasoning in the case. The problem remains, though: how can one distinguish in the reasoning of a judge the part that constitutes theratio decidendi and the part that constitutes obiter dicta? The issue of what exactly it is that constitutes theratio of a case is one that has been hugely debated by theorists of the common law. The debate is charted, and the different theories evaluated, most thoroughly by Cross and Harris (Cross and Harris 1991, 39–96). Complex though the debate is, there are fixed points of reference.
a) Judges will frequently say what they take to be the point of law at issue in a case. But even so the ratio decidendi cannot be equated to any such statement. The words the judge uses do not have canonical force, unlike the words of a statute. In a case governed by statute, a court faced with a situation in which the application of the statute is unclear cannot disregard the wording of statute. They must instead seek to interpret the wording of the statute, and discern its applicability by such a process. In the case of a statedratio, a later court is under no analogous obligation. It can legitimately state the ratio of the precedent case in different words than the judge(s) hearing the precedent case themselves used.
b) Moreover, it is simply not possible for a judge to create a legal norm simply by saying they are doing such a thing. The ratio decidendi in a case must have some internal relationship both to the actual facts of the instant case and to judgments that have been made in other cases. Also, the established semantics and syntax of natural language exercise influence (Stone 1968, 36).
c) The ratio cannot be equated with the actual reasoning given by a judge in favour of his or her decision, as that reasoning may be poor or worse from the point of view of legal science. Likewise, the ratio cannot be equated with any actual putative rule set forth by a judge, since it may be either broader or narrower than any such putative rule.
d) Despite the fact that the language of `rule’ is standardly used as a characterization of the ratio decidendi, it can be misleading to describe the ratio of a case as a `rule’. Neil MacCormick has argued that a ratio is more properly speaking a `ruling’ (MacCormick 1987, 179). An interpretation of a statute given in a case may come to be a precedent for future interpretations; but it is not the `rule’ in the case, the statute is. Moreover (and I will return to this later), it is frequently only clear after a series of future decisions that a precedent case stands for a given ratio. Once such a hardening process has taken place, then talk of the `rule’ in the original precedent case becomes appropriate. For all that, the case will have had a ratio at the time. Of course, if one thinks, as some do, that even the ratio of a case is subject to determination by later courts, then this proffered distinction between `rule’ and `ratio’ becomes much harder to make.
The two most plausible theories are those of A.L. Goodhart, and of Cross and Harris themselves. Goodhart has famously suggested that the ratio decidendi of a case is constituted by the principle that derives from thematerial facts of the case (Goodhart 1931, 1–36), or, more precisely, the facts that the judge treats as material facts in relation to the judgment the judge issues. He is careful to note that facts may be treated as materially either implicitly or explicitly. Goodhart is right to point out that, in the total fact situation of any actual case, some facts will matter from the legal point of view and some will not. That the accused was seen driving away from the bank at high speed moments after the robbery matters; that the accused was driving a Ford does not; unless matter of identification are at issue, in which case it might matter; and so on. Even if one recognizes that there will be some interdependence between the principle for which a case is thought to stand, and the facts of the case thought to be material, the advantage of Goodhart’s approach — to have the concept of `material fact’ drive the concept of ratio — is that it makes easier the preservation of the non-
Cross and Harris propose the following understanding of ratio decidendi: `The ratio decidendi of a case is any rule of law expressly or impliedly treated by the judge as a necessary step in reaching his conclusion, having regard to the line of reasoning adopted by him, or a necessary part of his direction to the jury’ (Cross, et al. 1991, 72). Such an account captures many of the fixed points enumerated above, and is therefore an attractive proposal. The difficulty in the proposal is this. Whatever the ratio decidendi of a case is, it is something that is determinative or dispositive. That is, the ratio is not merely necessary but also in some sense sufficient for the decision in the case. It is not clear how Cross’ and Harris’ proposal explains this element of sufficiency.
References
Cross, R., and J. Harris. 1991. Precedent in English Law. 4th edn. Clarendon Law Series. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Goodhart, A. 1931. Essays in Jurisprudence and the Common Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
MacCormick, N. 1987. `Why Cases have Rationes and What These Are’. In Precedent in Law, ed. L. Goldstein, 155–82. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Stone, J. 1968. Legal System and Lawyers’ Reasonings. Sydney: Maitland Publications Pty. Ltd.