Yale Law School Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository
Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship
1-1-1917 Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning
Wesley N. Hohfeld Yale Law School
Follow this and additional works at:http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers Part of theLegal History, Theory and Process Commons
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship at Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship Series by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contactjulian.aiken@yale.edu.
Recommended Citation Hohfeld, Wesley N., "Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning" (1917).Faculty Scholarship Series.Paper 4378. http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/4378
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS AS APPLIED IN JUDICIAL REASONING'
The present discussion, while intended to be intrinsically com- plete so far as intelligent and convenient perusal is concerned, represents, as originally planned, a continuation of an article which appeared under the same title more than three years ago.2 It therefore seems desirable to indicate, in very general form, the scope and purpose of the latter. The main divisions were entitled: Legal Conceptions Contrasted with Non-legal Concep- tions; Operative Facts Contrasted with Evidential Facts; and Fundamental Jural Relations Contrasted with One Another. The jural relations analyzed and discussed under the last subtitle were, at the outset, grouped in a convenient "scheme of opposites and correlatives";3 and it will greatly facilitate the presentation of the matters to be hereafter considered if that scheme be repro- duced at the present point: Jural X right privilege power immunity Opposites no-right duty disability liability
Jural X right privilege power immunity Correlatives l duty no-right liability disability
The great practical importance of accurate thought and pre- cise expression as regards basic legal ideas and their embodi- ment in a terminology not calculated to mislead is not always fully realized-especially by the student not yet far advanced in
'COPYRIGHT, I9I7, by Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld. The substance of this article, with some expansion and much additional illustrative material from judicial opinions, will form part of a volume to appear shortly under the same title as that here given. 2 (9I3) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6, 59. One of the chief purposes of this earlier article was to establish a firm foundation for the analysis and discussion of complex jural interests, or aggregates of jural rela- tions,-the interest of the cestui que trust having been more especially in view. See (19I3) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6-20, and notes. This last- mentioned subject receives some incidental consideration in the pages following; but a more adequate treatment must be reserved for another occasion. 8 See (O9M3) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6, 30 ff., where the individual conceptions represented in the scheme are treated at length.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 7VI
his legal work; and it is even true that many an experienced lawyer has all too thoughtlessly assumed that those matters usually considered in works on so-called "jurisprudence-" are merely "academic" in character and devoid of substantial utility for the practitioner or judge. In order to dissipate, if possible, this fallacious notion-one so demonstrably unfortunate in its consequences as regards all departments of the law -the eight conceptions represented in the above scheme were analyzed and compared in great detail, the purpose having been not only to exhibit their intrinsic meaning and scope and their relations to
'See Mr. Justice Holmes, The Path of the Law (I897) IO HARv. L. REV. 456, 474-475: "Jurisprudence, as I look at it, is simply law in its most gen- eralized part. Every effort to reduce a case to a rule is an effort of jurisprudence, although the name as used in English is confined to the broadest rules and most fundamental conceptions. One mark of a great lawyer is that he sees the application of the broadest rules. There is a story of a Vermont justice of the peace before whom a suit was brought by one farmer against another for break- ing a churn. The justice took time to consider, and then said that he had looked through the statutes and could find nothing about churns, and gave judgment for the defendant. The same state of mind is shown in all our common digests and text-books. Applica- tions of rudimentary rules of contract or tort are tucked away under the head of Railroads or Telegraphs or go to swell treatises on historical subdivisions, such as Shipping or Equity, or are gath- ered under an arbitrary title which is thought likely to appeal to the practical mind, such as Mercantile Law. If a man goes into law it pays to be a master of it, and to be a master of it means to look straight through all the dramatic incidents and to discern the true basis for prophecy. Therefore, it is well to have an accurate notion of what you mean by law, by a right, by a duty, by malice, intent, and negligence, by ownership, by possession, and so forth. I have in my mind cases in which the highest courts seem to me to have floundered because they had no clear ideas on some of these themes."
The following observations of the same learned judge are also deserving of consideration: "As long as the matter to be considered is debated in artificial terms there is a danger of being led by a technical definition to apply a certain name, and then to deduce consequences which have no relation to the grounds on which the name was applied." Mr. Justice Holmes in Guy v. Donald (i9o6) 203 U. S. 399, 406; 27 Sup. Ct. Rep. 63, 64. "It is one of the misfortunes of the law that ideas become encysted in phrases and thereafter for a long time cease to provoke further analysis." Mr. Justice Holmes, in Hyde v. United States (I9ii) 223 U. S. 347, 39I.
Compare the remarks of Lord Kinnear, in Bank of Scotland v. Macleod [1914] A. C. 3II, 324. He there endorses Lord Westbury's declaration that "there is not a more fruitful source of error in law than the inac-
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
712 YALE LAW JOURNAL
one another, but also to exemplify the methods, both good and bad, by which they are actually applied in judicial reasoning to the solution of concrete problems of litigation. The purpose last indicated must in the present discussion, as in the former one, be the justification for frequent concrete examples of judicial usage, and hence for liberal quotations from apposite judicial opinions. Instructive examples, whether by way of model or by way of warning, must also be drawn occasionally from the works of well-known legal authors.5 In the following pages it is proposed to begin the discussion of certain important classifications which are applicable to each of the eight individual jural conceptions represented in the above scheme. Some of such overspreading classifications consist of the following: relations in personam ("paucital" relations), and relations in rem ("multital" relations) ; common (or general) relations and special (or particular) relations; consensual rela- tions and constructive relations; primary relations and secondary relations; substantive relations and adjective relations; perfect relations and imperfect relations; concurrent relations (i. e., rela- tions concurrently legal and equitable) and exclusive relations (i. e., relations exclusively equitable)." As the bulk of our statute and case law becomes greater and greater, these classifications are constantly increasing in their practical importance: not only because of their intrinsic value as mental tools for the compre-
curate use of language," and Lord Mansfield's observation that "nothing in law is so apt to mislead as a metaphor." The learned judge also remarks: "The fallacy consists in using legal terms in a popular or meta- phorical sense and yet affixing to them all the legal consequences which would attach to their use in a strictly technical sense." See also, as regards confusion of thought resulting from loose or ambiguous legal terms, Field, J., in Morgan v. Louisiana (i876) 93 15. S. 2I7, 223; and Peckham, J., in Phoenix Ins. Co. v. Tennessee (i895) i6i U. S. I74, I77, I78. 'Owing, however, to. limitations of space, it has proved necessary to exclude at this time a large part of the available illustrative material originally intended to be presented. 6 For an explanation of the classification of jural relations as "con- current" and "exclusive" see the writer's article entitled, The Relations between Equity and Law (19I3) II Micn. L. REV. 537, 553, 569. See also the article of the writer's friend and colleague, Professor Walter Wheeler Cook, The Alienability of Choses in Action-A Reply to Professor Williston (1917) 30 HARV. L. REV. 449, 460 ff.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 713
hending and systematizing of our complex legal materials, but also because of the fact that the opposing ideas and terms involved are at the present time, more than ever before, con- stituting part of the formal foundation of judicial reasoning and decision.7 Owing to limitations of space the following pages will be confined to the first classification above indicated, viz., relations in personam and relations in rem. The phrases in personam and in rem, in spite of the scope and variety of situations to which they are commonly applied, are more usually assumed by lawyers, judges, and authors to be of unvarying meaning and free of ambiguities calculated to mislead the unwary. The exact opposite is, however, true; and this has occasionally been explicitly emphasized by able judges whose warnings are worthy Qf notice. Thus, in Tyler v. Court of Registration,8 Mr. Chief Justice Holmes says, as regards the expression, in rem, that "no phrase has been more misused"; and in the recent case of Hook v. Hoffman,9 Mr. Justice Franklin, in the course of a scholarly opinion involving the nature of "proceedings in rem," finds it necessary to characterize the expression "Jus in rem" as "somewhat obscure and ambiguous." The thoughtful judge last named is, however, kind enough to advise us of the one and only remedy for this difficulty, and prompt to apply that remedy in his own opinion. His words are worthy of quotation:
"It is no more of a solecism to say immovable personal property than it is to say removable fixtures, nor more contradicting than in the division of actions to use the term 'in rem,' when, under the particular state of facts, the action is primarily 'in personal.' In the development of the law it is seldom possible, or, when possible, seldom
'In this sentence the word "formal" must not be ignored; for, in emphasizing for the time being the formal and analytical side of legal problems, the writer would not be thought to underestimate the great importance of other phases of the law, both scientific and practical. He has had occasion elsewhere to discuss more comprehensively the funda- mental aspects of the law, including historical, or genetic, jurisprudence; comparative, or eclectic, jurisprudence; formal, or analytical, jurispru- dence; critical, or teleological, jurisprudence; legislative, or constructive, jurisprudence; empirical, or functional, jurisprudence.- See A Vital School of Jurisprudence and Law, PRoc. OF ASSN. OF AM. LAW SCHOOLS FOR 1914, Up. 76-139. (1900) 175 Mass. 71, 76. (1915) i6 Ariz. 540, 554.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
714 YALE LAW JOURNAL
expedient, to discard established terms. In this connection an observation by Mr. Justice Holmes is peculiarly applicable: 'As long as the matter to be considered is debated in artificial terms, there is danger of being led by a technical definition to apply a certain name, and then to deduce consequences which have no relation to the grounds on which the name was applied.' Guy v. Donald, 203 U. S. 406. "Instead of rejecting convenient terms because they are ambiguous or not comprehensive, it is better to explain their meanings, or, in the language of old Hobbes, 'to snuff them with distinctions and definitions,' so as to give a better light."'0
All this being so, we are forced to recognize at the very outset that the antithetical pair of expressions, in personam and in rem, is constantly being employed as a basis for classifying at least four distinct matters; and that the respective meanings of the expression in personam and the expression in rem are not the same for all of the different situations involved: First, we have a fundamental classification of primary rights as rights in personal, and rights in rem; Second, there is the well-known classification of all judicial proceedings into pro- ceedings or actions in personal and proceedings or actions in rem; Third, there exists the closely related classification of judgments and decrees (and the corresponding jurisdictions of courts), some being called judgments or decrees in personal, and the others judgments or decrees in rem; Fourth, assuming a judgment or decree in personam to have been obtained as the result of what may be called the "primary stage" of the typical judicial proceeding, the question of its so-called "enforcement"- really the "secondary stage" of the judicial proceeding-comes into view;" and such enforcement is said to be either in per-
10 (I9I5) i6 Ariz. 540, 558. Compare, as regards the significance and propriety of these terms, "primary stage" and "secondary stage" as applied to a suit in equity or an action at law, Lord Hardwicke, in Penn v. Lord Baltimore (1750) I Ves. 444, 454: "As to the court's not enforcing the execution of their judgment; if they could not at all, I agree, it would be in vain to make a decree; and that the court cannot inforce their own decree in rem, in the present case: but that is not an objection against making a decree in the cause; for the strict primary decree in this court
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 715
sonam, as in the case of the typical contempt proceeding employed to coerce performance of a decree in equity, or in rem, as in the case of the typical execution sale following upon an ordinary legal judgment in personal.12 Anyone who has seriously observed and reflected on the interrelation of ideas and language must realize how words tend to react upon ideas and to hinder or control them. More specifically, it is overwhelmingly clear that the danger of confusion is especially great when the same term or phrase is constantly used to express two or more distinct ideas. Professor Holland, having in mind, as regards this psychological phenomenon, a particular instance not now before us,- viz., the well-known ambiguity of the Latin jus, the German Recht, the Italian diritto, and the French droit, terms used to indicate both "law" as such and "a right" considered as a concrete relation created by law,-does not exaggerate in the least when he says:
"If the expression of widely different ideas by one and the same term resulted only in the necessity for these clumsy periphrases, or obviously inaccurate paraphrases, no great harm would be done; but unfortunately the
as a court of equity is in personal, long before it was settled, whether this court could issue [sic] to put into possession in a suit of lands in England; which was first begun and settled in the time of James I. but ever since done by injunction or writ of assistant to the sheriff: but the court cannot to this day as to lands in Ireland or the plantations. In Lord King's time in the case of Richardson v. Hamilton, Attorney General of Pennsylvania, which was a suit of land and a house in the town of Philadelphia, the court made a decree, though it could not be inforced in rem. In the case of Lord Anglesey of land lying in Ireland, I decreed for distinguishing and settling the parts of the estate, though impossible to inforce that decree in rem, but the party being in England, I could inforce it by process of contempt in personam and sequestra- tion, which is the proper jurisdiction of this court."
It is interesting to observe that Lord Hardwicke speaks of the writ of assistance (under which an equity plaintiff might through the sheriff be put into actual possession of land) as a means by which a court of equity could at times "enforce in rem" the "strict primary decree in personam." 12 For an able and searching discussion of proceedings in personal and proceedings in rem, see the series of articles by Professor Walter Wheeler Cook entitled, The Powers of Courts of Equity (1915) I5 COL. L. REV. 37, I o6, 228. See also the present writer's article The Relations between Equity and Law (1913) II MICH. L. REV. 537, passion.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
7I6 YALE LAW JOURNAL
identity of terms seems irresistibly to suggest an identity between the ideas which are expressed by them."'-3
No doubt this psychological and linguistic principle-what might be called "the principle of linguistic contamination"- explains why certain well-known legal authors have assumed, with unfortunate effect on their reasoning and argument, that the contrasted pairs of terms in personam and in rem have the same intrinsic meaning in each of the four cases above mentioned, and therefore represent throughout a precisely similar basis of classification; also that there is some formal and symmetrical interdependence between the four classifications presented,-e. g., that primary rights in rem are such as may be "enforced," or vindicated, by proceedings and judgments in rem, or, similarly, that primary rights in personam are such as can be "enforced," or vindicated, only by actions or proceedings in personam. At a later point some of these problems and fallacies will receive incidental treatment in connection with the main thread of the discussion, and it will thus be possible to give more concrete specifications and examples. The chief purpose of the following pages is, however, to discuss, directly and exhaustively, only the first of the four general classifications above outlined, i. e., rights (or claims), privileges, powers, and immunities in per- sonam and rights (or claims), privileges, powers, and immunities in rem. Substituting what the writer ventures to suggest as equivalent and more satisfactory terms for the phrases in per- sonam and in rem, we shall have to deal seriatim with eight classifications, as follows: i. paucital rights (or claims) and multital rights (or claims); 2. paucital privileges and multital
3Holland, Jurisp. (ioth ed., i906) pp. 8o-8i. Compare Austin, Jurisp. (5th ed., i885) Vol. I, pp. 285-286, note, referring to the same ambiguity as Holland, and adding:
"Since the strongest and wariest minds are often ensnared by ambiguous words, their (the Germans') confusion of those disparate objects is a venial error."
Compare also Austin, Jurisp., Vol. I, p. 322, note:
"In the language of English jurisprudence, facts or events which are contracts quasi or uti, are styled implied contracts, or contracts which the law implies: that is to say, contracts quasi or uti, and genuine though tacit contracts, are denoted by a common name, or by names nearly alike. And, consequently, contracts, quasi or uti, and implied or tacit contracts, are commonly or frequently confounded by English lawyers. See, in particular, Sir William Blackstone's Commentaries, B. II. Ch. 30. and B. III. Ch. 9."
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 717
privileges; 3. paucital powers and multital powers; 4. paucital immunities and multital immunities; 5. paucital no-rights and multital no-rights; 6. paucital duties and multital duties; 7. paucital disabilities and multital disabilities; 8. paucital liabilities and multital liabilities. Each of these eight definite classifications must, for the sake of clearness, receive somewhat separate treatment. Owing, however, to limitations of space, the present article will deal chiefly with the first subdivision, i. e., paucital rights, or claims, and multital rights, or claims. As more fully shown in the former article, the word "right" is used generically and indiscriminately to denote any sort of legal advantage, whether claim, privilege, power, or immunity.'4 In its narrowest sense, however, the term is used as the correlative of duty ;"5 and, to convey this meaning, the synonym "claim" seems the best.'6 In what follows, therefore, the term "right" will be used solely in that very limited sense according to which it is the correlative of duty. It is hoped that the meaning and importance of this needful discrimination may gain in concrete- ness and clearness as further details and examples come into view.
For judicial opinions recognizing the broad and generic significance of this term when loosely used, see the authorities discussed in (1913) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6, 30 ff. Compare also, to similar effect, Slater, J., in Shaw v. Proffitt (i9io) 57 Or. I92, 20I:
"It is strenuously urged by defendant's counsel that, under the pleadings in this case, plaintiff stands on a bare parol license, which he claims to have obtained from the defendant and his predecessors in interest and that, therefore, plaintiff is precluded from obtaining the full effect of his evidence. We do not agree with such restricted interpretation of the language found in the complaint. It is averred that plaintiff obtained the 'right' as well as the 'consent, per- mission and license of defendant and his predecessors.' The word 'right' denotes, among other things, 'property,' 'interest,' 'power,' 'prerogative,' 'immunity,' and 'privilege,' and in law is most fre- quently applied to property in its restricted sense."
See (1913) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6, 3I-32. In this connection, the language of Mr. Justice Stayton, though not recommended for precision, may well be compared:
"A right has been well defined to be a well-founded claim, and a well-founded claim means nothing more nor less than a claim recognized or secured by law. "Rights which pertain to persons, other than such as are termed natural rights, are essentially the creatures of municipal law, written or unwritten, and it must necessarily be held that a right, in a legal sense, exists, when in consequence of given facts the law declares that one person is entitled to enforce against another a claim Mellinger v. City of Huston (i887) 68 Tex. 37, 45; 3 S. W. 249, 253.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
718 YALE LAW JOURNAL
It is necessary at this point to venture a preliminary explana- tion of the division or classification now before us-confessing at once that it represents a departure from accepted modes of statement or definition on the part of learned authors and judges. It will then remain for the more detailed discussion and argument to show, if possible, that the currently received explanations are not only essentially faulty as regards analysis but also seriously misleading for the very practical purpose of solving legal prob- lems as swiftly and accurately as possible. A paucital right, or claim, (right in personal) is either a unique right residing in a person (or group of persons) and availing against a single person (or single group of persons)17; or else it is one of a few fundamentally similar, yet separate, rights availing respectively against a few definite persons.'8 A multital right, or claim, (right in rem) is always one of a large class of fundamentally similar yet separate rights, actual and potential,'9 residing in a single person (or single group of per- sons) but availing respectively against persons constituting a very large and indefinite class of people.20 Probably all would agree substantially on the meaning and significance of a right in personam, as just explained; and it is easy to give a few preliminary examples: If B owes A a thou- sand dollars, A has an affirmative right in personal, or paucital right, that B shall transfer to A the legal ownership of that amount of money. If, to put a contrasting situation, A already
1 The words "group of persons" are intended to cover cases of so-called "joint" rights and duties. 8 While the word "paucital" is suggested as the generic term to cover all rights in personam, the word "unital" would be available to denote that particular kind of right in personam that is "unique" and "uncom- panioned." 19 The reasons for including the words, "actual and potential" must be discussed at a later time, after a general consideration of the distinc- tion between "actual" and "potential" jural relations. 'It is not infrequently thought that the word "general" is both appro- priate and available to denote those rights, or claims, that are here called "multital." See, e. g., Markby, Elements of Law (6th ed., 1905) sec. i65. It is submitted, however, that according to the best usage the term "general," as applied to a jural relation, indicates that the latter is one of a large class of similar relations residing respectively in many persons, i. e., people in general. For example, any duty correlating with a multital right would be a general, or common, duty. The right of a person not to be struck by another is both multital and general. This matter will receive more complete consideration at a later time.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 719
has title to one thousand dollars, his rights against others in relation thereto are multital rights, or rights in rem. In the one case the money is owed to A; in the other case it is owned by A.21 If Y has contracted to work for X during the ensuing six months, X has an affirmative right in personam that Y shall render such service, as agreed. Similarly as regards all other contractual or quasi-contractual rights of this character. On the other hand, there may occasionally be rights in personal. of a negative tenor or content. Thus if K, a distinguished opera singer, contracts with J that the former will not for the next three months sing at any rival opera house, J has a negative right in personal against K; and the latter is under a correlative negative duty. In this, as in other cases of rights in the sense of claims, the right of J is but one phase of the total relation between J and K, and the duty of K is another phase of the same relation,-that is, the whole "right-duty" relation may be viewed from different angles. In contrast to these examples are those relating to rights, or claims, in rem-i. e., multital rights. If A owns and occupies Whiteacre, not only B but also a great many other persons- not necessarily all persons22-are under a duty, e. g., not to enter on A's land. A's right against B is a multital right, or right in rem, for it is simply one of A's class of similar, though separate, rights, actual and potential, against very many persons. The same points apply as regards A's right that B shall not commit a battery on him, A's right that B shall not alienate the affections of A's wife, and A's right that B shall not manu- facture a certain article as to which A has a so-called patent.
'Compare Pollock and Maitland, History of English Law (2d ed., I905) Vol. II, p. I78. ' It is sometimes assumed that rights in rem (considered collectively) are such only as avail against absolutely all persons,-an idea fostered in part by the frequently-used expression "against all the world." See, e. g., Langdell, Summary of Equity Pleading (2d ed., i883) sec. i84; Langdell, Brief Survey of Equity Jurisdiction (i887) i HARV. L. REV. 6o; Hart, The Place of Trusts in Jurisprudence (i9i2) 28 LAW QUART. REV. 290, 296; Terry, The Arrangement of the Law (I7I7) I7 COL. L. REV. 365, 376. This notion is not warranted according to general usage. If, for example, A, the owner of Blackacre, has given his friends C and D, "leave and license" to enter, A has no rights against C and D that they shall not enter; but he has such rights against persons in general; and they are clearly to be classified as being "multital" or "in rem." For further phases of this matter, see ante, p. 7i8 n. I9; post, PP. 754-760.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
720 YALE LAW JOURNAL
Further examples of such negativee23 multital rights will readily occur to the reader. Other important instances will require detailed consideration from time to time. In spite of the formal and abstract explanations already given, and in spite of the concrete examples added for merely pre- liminary purposes, the effort to give an incisive and compre- hensive appreciation of the conceptual and linguistic difficulties and dangers involved in the expressions under consideration would doubtless fail, at least as regards the inexperienced student, unless considerably more were done by way of direct discussion of common errors. That is to say, it seems necessary to show very concretely and definitely how, because of the unfortunate terminology involved, the expression "right in rem" is all too frequently misconceived, and meanings attributed to it that could not fail to blur and befog legal thought and argument. Some of these loose and misleading usages will now be considered in detail, it being hoped that the more learned reader will remember that this discussion, being intended for the assistance of law school students more than for any other class of persons, is made more detailed and elementary than would otherwise be necessary. (a) A right in rem is not a right "against a thing": In Hook v. Hoffman24 we are told by Mr. Justice Franklin, in hopeful vein, that "the somewhat obscure and ambiguous expression 'jus in rem,' when standing by itself, catches a borrowed clear- ness from the expression 'jus in personal, to which it is opposed."25 This is laudable optimism! It cannot, however, be shared by one who has, in the course of many years, observed not only the ways and tendencies of many hundreds of intelligent students, but also the not unnatural slips of the more learned. Any person, be he student or lawyer, unless he has contemplated the matter analytically and assiduously, or has been put on notice by books or other means, is likely, first, to translate right in
23 As indicated by the examples given, multital rights are always con- structive rather than consensual; that is, they and their correlating duties arise independently of even an approximate expression of intention on the part of those concerned. This explains, no doubt, why most, if not all, of such duties are negative in character: it is just and politic to spread such merely negative duties broadcast; whereas precisely the opposite would be true in the case of most kinds of affirmative duties. 24 (19I5) i6 Ariz. 540, 555. Compare, for precisely similar language, Austin, Jurisp. (5th ed., i885) Vol. II, p. 957.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 72 1
personam as a right against a person; and then he is almost sure to interpret right in rem, naturally and symmetrically as he thinks, as a right against a thing. Assuming that the division represented by in personam and in rem is intended to be mutually exclusive, it is plausible enough to assume also that if a right in personam is simply a right against a person, a right in rem must be a right that is not against a person, but against a thing. That is, the expression right in personam, standing alone, seems to encourage the impression that there must be rights that are not against persons. Then, of course, such a supposed, though erroneous, contrast is further encouraged by the prima facie literal meaning of the Latin phrase in rem, considered per se; for it cannot be assumed that the average person is acquainted with the peculiar history and special meaning of that phrase. Such a notion of rights in rem is, as already intimated, crude and fallacious; and it can but serve as a stumbling-block to clear thinking and exact expression. A man may indeed sustain close and beneficial physical relations to a given physical thing: he may physically control and use such thing, and he may physically exclude others from any similar control or enjoyment. But, obviously, such purely physical relations could as well exist quite apart from, or occasionally in spite of, the law of organized society: physical relations are wholly distinct from jural rela- tions.26 The latter take significance from the law; and, since the purpose of the law is to regulate the conduct of human beings, all jural relations must, in order to be clear and direct in their meaning, be predicated of such human beings. The words of able judges may be quoted as showing their realization of the practical importance of the point now being emphasized: i900, Mr. Chief Justice Holmes, in Tyler v. Court of Regis- tration :2 "All proceedings, like all rights, are really against per- sons. Whether they are proceedings or rights in rem depends on the number of persons affected."28
2 As to the prevalent and unfortunate tendency to confuse legal and non-legal conceptions, see the more general discussion in (1913) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, I6, 20 ff.; see also post, p. 725, n. 34; and p. 755, n. go. 2( 900) I75 Mass. 7I, 76. 'Compare also the following from Mr. Justice Holmes' opinion: "It is true as an historical fact that these symbols are used in admiralty proceedings, and also, again merely as an historical fact, that the proceedings in rem have been confined to cases where
53
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
722 YALE LAW JOURNAL
i905, Mr. Justice Markby, Elements of Law:29
"If we attempt to translate the phrase [in rem] liter- ally, and get it into our heads that a thing, because rights exist in respect of it, becomes a sort of juristical person, and liable to duties, we shall get into endless confusion."30
What is here insisted on,-i. e., that all rights in rem are against persons,-is not to be regarded merely as a matter of
certain classes of claims, although of very divers sorts,-for indemnification for injury, for wages, for salvage, etc.,-are to be asserted. But a ship is not a person. It cannot do a wrong or make a contract. To say that a ship has committed a tort is merely a shorthand way of saying that you have decided to deal with it as if it had committed one, because some man has committed one in fact. There is no a priori reason why any other claim should not be enforced in the same way. If a claim for a wrong committed by a master may be enforced against all interests in the vessel, there is no juridical objection to a claim of title being enforced in the same way. The fact that it is not so enforced under existing practice affords no test of the powers of the Legis- lature. The contrary view Would indicate that you really believed the fiction that a vessel had an independent personality as a fact behind the law." (1900) I75 Mass. 7I, 77. 29 (6th ed., I905) sec. i65. ' To say that all rights, or claims, must be against persons is, of course, simply another way of asserting that all duties must be predicated of persons. The latter is, in truth, no less obvious than the proposition that all rights must be predicated of persons. Compare Mr. Justice Markby, in his Elements of Law (6th ed., I905) sec. i63: "The chief, in my opinion the only, use of a division of law into the law of persons and the law of things is as a convenient arrangement of topics in a treatise or a code. As used for this purpose I shall speak of it hereafter. But by slightly changing the terms in which this classification is expressed, Blackstone has introduced an important error, which it is desirable to notice here. He speaks not of the law of persons and of the law of things, but of rights of persons and of rights of things. Rights of per- sons there are undoubtedly; for all rights are such. There may be also rights over things, and rights over persons; but rights of, that is, belonging to, things, as opposed to rights of, that is, belonging to, persons, there cannot be."
Compare also Mr. Justice Henshaw in Western Indemnity Co. v. Pillsbury (19I5) 170 Cal. 686, 719: "Again it is said that it is thought expedient that the loss by injuries to workmen should be borne by the industries and not by the men. But this is only a euphemism which obscures the facts and darkens reason. It is like other happy catch-phrases that deceive the mind by pleasing the ear. We have many such. 'Putting the rights of property before the rights of men,' is one- as though property apart from those of its human owner, ever did or could have any rights. So that the rights of property are absolutely the rights of men."
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 723
taste or preference for one out of several equally possible forms of statement or definition. Logical consistency seems to demand such a conception, and nothing less than that. Some concrete examples may serve to make this plain. Suppose that A is the owner of Blackacre and X is the owner of Whiteacre. Let it be assumed, further, that, in consideration of $ioo actually paid by A to B,31 the latter agrees with A never to enter on X's land, Whiteacre. It is clear that A's right against B concerning White- acre is a right in personal, or paucital right; for A has no similar and separate rights concerning Whiteacre availing respec- tively against other persons in general. On the other hand, A's right against B concerning Blackacre is obviously a right in rem, or multital right; for it is but one of a very large number of fundamentally similar (though separate) rights which A has respectively against B., C, D, E, F, and a great many other per- sons. It must now be evident, also, that A's Blackacre right against B is, intrinsically considered, of the same general char- acter as A's Whiteacre right against B. The Blackacre right differs, so to say, only extrinsically, that is, in having many fun- damentally similar, though distinct, rights as its "companions." So, in general, we might say that a right in personal is one having few, if any, "companions"; whereas a right in rem always has many such "companions." If, then, the Whiteacre right, being a right in personal, is recognized as a right against a person, must not the Blackacre right also, being, point for point, intrinsically of the same gen- eral nature, be conceded to be a right against a person? If not that, what is it? How can it be apprehended, or described, or delimited at all?. If it be said that, as regards Blackacre, A has besides his rights, or claims, against B, C, D, E, and others, various legal privileges of controlling and using the land, and that these exist "to, over, or against" the land, one answer might be that as regards White- acre also A has similar privileges against B., C, D, E and all others excepting X, the true owner. But the really relevant and paramount reply at this point is that we are now dealing only with multital rights, or claims, and not with multital privileges. The latter will require attention in a later part of the discussion.82
I" The consideration being actually paid to B, the validity of B's promise to A is, of course, not subject to question merely because B was already under a similar duty to X. " See post, pp. 745-752.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
724 YALE LAW JOURNAL
It may, however, even at this point be incidentally noticed that the general tendency to "confuse" or "blend" legal privileges with legal rights, or claims, has doubtless contributed greatly to the hazy conception of a right in rem as a right to, over, or against a thing. For the reasons already given the following passages from legal treatises and judicial opinions seem open to question in one or more particulars: I874, Mr. Stephen Martin Leake, Law of Property in Land:
"Jurisprudence distinguishes Rights, using the term in the strict legal meaning, into the two classes of Rights to Things and Rights against Persons, familiarly known in the civil law by the terms jura in rem and jura in per- sonam. "Rights to things, jura in rem, have for their subject some material thing, as land or goods, which the owner may use or dispose of in any manner he pleases within the limits prescribed by the terms of his right. A right of this kind imports in all persons generally the correlative negative duty of abstaining from any interference with the exercise of it by the owner; and by enforcing this duty the law protects and establishes the right. But a right of this kind does not import any positive duty in any deter- minate person, or require any act or intervention of such person for its exercise and enjoyment. "Rights against persons, jura in personal, on the other hand, have for their subject an act or performance of some certain determinate person, as the payment of money, the delivery of goods and the like. A right of this kind imports the correlative positive legal duty in the deter- minate person to act in the manner prescribed. It depends for its exercise or enjoyment upon the performance of that duty, and is secured by the legal remedies provided for a breach of performance. . "Rights to things, jura in rem, vary and are distin- guished according to the things or material subjects in the use or disposal of which the right consists."33
The learned author, whose work is well known to law students and highly valued for its general clearness and accuracy, has been unfortunate in treating "in rem" as if it meant "to a thing'; and it would seem that he was influenced to do this, partly at least, as a result of confusing legal privileges and legal rights. More than that, this first error has led to an additional
#Law of Property in Land (ist ed., 1874) pp. I, 2.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 725
one: that of conveying the impression that all rights in rem (multital rights), in order to be such, must relate to a material thing. Such a limitation would exclude not only many rights in rem, or multital rights, relating to persons, but also those con- stituting elements of patent interests, copyright interests, etc. Finally the learned author falls into the error of asserting that all rights in personam are affirmative in character; whereas they may occasionally be negative, as heretofore seen. i9i6, Professor Joseph Henry Beale, Treatise on Conflict of Laws:
"The nature of rights.-The primary purpose of law being the creation of rights, and the chief task of the Conflict of Laws to determine the place where a right arose and the law that created it, a more careful study of the nature of rights is of course desirable before the examination of actual cases of conflict is begun. . "Since we are fortunate enough to have different words for these ideas [law and rights] it is all the more neces- sary that we should fully understand each of them. "A right may be defined as a legally recognized inter- est in, to, or against a person or a thing."34
'Beale, Treatise on Conflict of Laws (I9I6) sec. 139. All will agree with Professor Beale that, for accurate thinking and correct results in the conflict of laws, it is of vital importance to have sound and consistent conceptions of legal rights and other jural relations; and it is evident that, pursuant to this idea, much of the learned author's reasoning and very many of his arguments and conclusions on specific problems in the conflict of laws have, very naturally, been directly based on his "pre- liminary survey" of "rights" and on his supposed distinction between what he calls "static rights" and what he calls "dynamic rights." Yet it may be doubted whether Professor Beale has made clear and consistent his conception of a so-called "static right," as "a legally recognized interest in, to, or against a person or a thing"; and thus one is forced the more to question the validity of many of his arguments and conclusions in the closely related fields of jurisprudence and conflict of laws. At one time the "static right" seems to be a purely factual "interest" existing independently of law; at another time a relation "created by law." The former idea is suggested when the learned author refers to Gareis's definition of "interests." This appears very clearly not only from the intrinsic meaning of Gareis's language as quoted by Professor Beale, but also from certain introductory words which are to be found in Gareis's original work: "Interests, considered as facts, arise directly from egoism, and are nothing other than subjectively perceived relations," etc. See Gareis, Systematic Survey (Kocourek's translation) p. 31. Indeed, Professor Beale himself, in the very definition quoted in the text of the
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
726 YALE LAW JOURNAL
I903, Mr. Herbert Thorndyke Tiffany, Modern Lazw of Real Property:
"Powers of attorney, by which one person is nominated as an agent to make a transfer or do some other act in the name and stead of the principal, are sometimes spoken of as common-law powers. Such an authority, however, while it did exist as common law, is entirely different from the powers here considered (i. e., powers of appoint- ment), since it is merely an agency in the person to whom the power is given, authorizing him to execute an instru- ment of conveyance or to do some other act in the place and stead of his principal, the title passing, not by the power of attorney, but by the conveyance subsequently made, which is regarded as made by the principal. A power of attorney creates merely a contractual relation,-rights in personasn,-as does any other contract of agency; while a power, such as we here treat of, involving dominion over land to a greater or less extent, creates in the person to whom the power is given rights in rem of a proprietary character."35
The exact meaning of the learned author is not evident; but
present article, defines "a right" as an "interest," not as some legal relation protecting the interest: there is a very obvious difference-and one vitally important for the solution of problems in the conflict of laws- between a mere factual interest and its legal recognition (legal claims, privileges, etc.). In sec. 141, however, we find the following: "A static right, or as it is commonly called a vested interest, is a legally protected interest in a person or thing. Such an interest is one which continues indefinitely, and protection of it therefore requires a right which, like the interest it protects, has the character of permanence. Accordingly a static right remains in existence until either the subject of the interest ceases to exist or the law itself by a special act puts an end to the right." In this passage we are told first, that a "static right" is an interest; second, that the "right" is something other than "the interest it protects"; third, that "a static right remains in existence until . . . . the law itself . . . . puts an end to the right." A similar sudden and difficult shift seems to occur in sec. i42. Thus: "A static right, as has been seen, is the interest of a person in a thing or in a person; the right is created by law, and once created it is permanent, that is, it persists until the proper law puts an end to it. The law that creates it, as will be seen, also provides for its preservation, by creating a hedge of protecting rights about it; rights of the owner or possessor to have it free from interference or destruction. . It is to be regarded as a legal entity quite apart from the particular protection with which it may be endued by law." '~Modern Law of Real Property (i9o3) sec. 273.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 727
it seems clear that the power of an agent to convey Whiteacre is not intrinsically different, so long as it endures, from a power to convey Whiteacre in exercise of a so-called power of appoint- ment. It is true that the agent is subject to a liability of having his power "revoked" or divested by the principal, whereas the power of appointment is subject to no similar liability at the hands of anyone. But this difference, conceding its great im- portance, is, of course, not accurately expressed by asserting that the power of attorney creates rights in personal, and the power of appointment "creates in the person to whom the power is given rights in rem of a proprietary character." In truth the creation of a power of agency does not necessarily involve any contract rights against the principal or any one else.36 The fact seems to be that the greater "staying" quality of the power of appointment (as compared with the power of agency) has sug- gested to the author greater "adhesiveness" or "thingness," and hence caused the inappropriate terms now under review. Further critical consideration of the last-quoted passage will be desirable in connection with the subject of immunities in personam and immunities in rem. i828, Sir Thomas Plumer, M.R., in Dearle v. Hall:
"They say, that they were not bound to give notice to the trustees; for that notice does not form part of the necessary conveyance of an equitable interest. I admit, that, if you mean to rely on contract with the individual, you do not need to give notice; from the moment of the contract, he, with whom you are dealing, is personally bound. But if you mean to go further, and to make your right attach upon the thing which is the subject of the contract, it is necessary to give notice; and, unless notice is given, you do not do that which is essential in all cases of transfer of personal property. . . . Notice, then, is necessary to perfect the title,-to give a complete right in rem, and not merely a right as against him who conveys his interest."37
This passage from Dearle v. Hall will require further treat- ment in connection with the subject of immunities in personam and immunities in rem. i857, Mr. Justice Cutting, in Redington v. Frye:
"But a sub-contractor has no claim against the owner of the property-his claim is only against the property
WSee Huffcut, Agency (2d ed., i9oi) sec. IO. ' (1828) 3 Russ. I, 22, 24.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
728 YALE LAW JOURNAL
(in rem), and the person and property of his employer (in personal).".38
The preceding quotations from legal treatises and judicial opinions have been presented, as is evident, for the purpose of exemplifying the less careful and exact use of terms that we sometimes find, and for the further purpose of indicating the confusion of thought that is likely to result in such cases. Over against these will now be considered various passages from legal treatises and judicial opinions exemplifying more precise modes of thought and expression. It is desirable to begin with Austin; for his work on Jurisprudence was the first to give prominence to the terms right in rem and right in personal among English- speaking lawyers and authors, and his language has become classical in its importance: i832, Professor John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence or The Philosophy of Positive Law:
"The distinction between Rights which I shall presently endeavour to explain, is that all-pervading and important distinction which has been assumed by the Roman Insti- tutional Writers as the main groundwork of their arrange- ment: namely, ,the distinction between rights in rem and rights in personal; or rights which avail against persons generally or universally, and rights which avail exclusively against certain or determinate persons.38
(i857) 43 Me. 578, 587. 3The pair of terms, "jus in personal and "jus in rem" as contrasted with the pair of terms, actiono in personal" and actiono in rem," was not in general use among the Roman jurists. Compare Clark, History of Roman Law: Jurisprudence, Vol. II, p. 71: "Jus in rem and Jus in re in Roman Law. The former of these expressions is very little used by the Roman Jurists, but, in the few passages in which it occurs, res clearly means the thing itself as distinguished e. g. from its value. (See Ulpian, Dig. 32. 20. Nullum quidem jus in ipsam rem habere, sed actionem de pretio. Cf. Goudsmit, 247 n.)" It is clear, therefore, that the "all-pervading and important" Roman law distinction to which Austin refers was that represented by obligatio and dominium. Compare Austin, Jurisp. (5th ed., i885) Vol. I, p. 383: "By jus in rem and jus in personal, the authors of those terms intended to indicate this broad and simple distinction; which the Roman lawyers also marked by the words dominium and obligatio-terms the distinction between which was the groundwork of all their attempts to arrange rights and duties in an accurate or scientific manner." Also Austin, Jurisp., Vol. II, p. 773: "The first great distinction among primary rights has been very fully explained in a preceding part of this Course. I allude to the
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 729
"The terms 'jus in rem' and 'jus in personal' were devised by the Civilians of the Middle Ages, or arose in times still more recent. "The phrase in rem denotes the compass, and not the subject of the right. It denotes that the right in question avails against persons generally; and not that the right in question is a right over a thing. For, as I shall show hereafter, many of the rights, which are jura or rights in rem, are either rights over, or to, persons, or have no subject (person or thing). "The phrase in personal is an elliptical or abridged expression for 'in personam certam sive determinatam.' Like the phrase in rem, it denotes the compass of the right. It denotes that the right avails exclusively against a determinate person, or against determinate persons."4?
Additional explanations of ideas and terms and further in- structive examples of usage are to be found in the following utterances of able judges: I87I, Mr. Justice Markby, Elements of Law:
"The term 'right in rem' is a very peculiar one; trans- lated literally it would mean nothing. The use of it in conjunction with the term 'in personal' as the basis of a classification of actions in the Roman law has been explained above, and its meaning will be further illus- trated by two passages in the Digest of Justinian. In Book iv. tit. 2. sec. 9, the rule of law is referred to- that what is done under the influence of fear should not be binding: and commenting on this it is remarked, that the lawgiver speaks here generally and 'in rem,' and does not specify any particular kind of persons who cause the fear; and that therefore the rule of law applies, whoever the person may be. Again, in Book xliv. tit. 4. sec. 2, it is laid down that, in what we should call a plea of fraud, it must be specially stated whose fraud is com- plained of, 'and not in rem.' On the other hand, it is pointed out that, if it is shown whose fraud is complained of, it is sufficient; and it need not be said whom the fraud was intended to injure; for (says the author of the Digest) the allegation that the transaction is void, by reason of the fraud of the person named, is made 'in rem.' In all these three cases 'in rem' is used as an adverb, and I think we should express as nearly as
distinction between dominia and obligationes, as they were called by the classical jurists; between jura in rem and jura in personal, as they have been styled by modern Civilians." '4Jurisp. (5th ed., i885) Vol. I, pp. 369, 370.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
730 YALE LAW JOURNAL
possible its exact equivalent, if we substituted for it the English word 'generally.' In the phrase 'right in rem' it is used as an adjective, and the equivalent English expression would be a 'general right'; but a more ex- plicit phrase is a 'right availing against the world at large': and if this, which is the true meaning of the phrase 'right in rem,' be carefully remembered, no mistake need occur."'41
i883, Mr. Justice Mulkey, in W., St. L. & P. Ry. Co. v. Shacklet:
"One of the primary rights of the citizen, sanctioned by the positive law of the State, is security to life and limb, and indemnity against personal injuries occasioned by the negligence, fraud or violence of others. This is a right which avails against all persons whomsoever, and is dis- tinguished from a right which avails against a par- ticular individual or a determinate class of persons. The former is called a right in rem, the latter a right in per- sonam. The former class of rights exists independently of contract; the latter frequently arises out of contract.... "So in the present case, appellee's intestate had a right in rem, or a general right, which entitled him, if free from fault himself, to be protected and indemnified against in- juries resulting from the negligence of all persons whom- soever, including the appellant. . . ."42
i886, Mr. Justice Holmes, in Hogan v. Barry:
"There is no doubt that an easement may be created by words sounding in covenant. Bronson v. Coffin, io8 Mass. I75, i8o. If the seeming covenant is for a present enjoy- ment of a nature recognized by the law as capable of being conveyed and made an easement,-capable, that is to say, of being treated as a jus in rem, and as not merely the subject of a personal undertaking,-and if the deed dis- closes that the covenant is for the benefit of adjoining land conveyed at the same time, the covenant must be construed as a grant, and, as is said in Plowden, 308, 'the phrase of speech amounts to the effect to vest a present property in you.' An easement will be created and attached to the land conveyed, and will pass with it to assigns, whether mentioned in the grant or not."43
'4 Elements of Law (6th ed., 1905) sec. i65. 42 (i883) 105 III. 364, 379. ' (i886) 143 Mass. 538.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 731
I903, Mr. Justice Holmes, in International Postal Supply Co. v. Bruce:
"As the United States could not be made a party the suit failed. In the case at bar the United States is not the owner of the machines, it is true, but it is a lessee in possession, for a term which has not expired. It has a property, a right in rem, in the machines, which, though less extensive than absolute ownership, has the same inci- dent of a right to use them while it lasts."44
i904, Mr. Justice Holmes, in Baltimore Shipbuilding Co. v. Baltimore:
"In the next place, as to the interest of the United States in the land. This is a mere condition subsequent. There is no easement or present right in rem. The obligation to keep up the dock and to allow the United States to use it carries active duties and is purely personal. . .. The United States has no present right to the land, but merely a personal claim against the corporation, reinforced by a condition."'45
I905, Mr. Justice Holmes, in Muhlker v. Harlem R. R. Co.:
"What the plaintiff claims is really property, a right in rem. It is called contract merely to bring it within the contract clause of the Constitution."46
I913, Viscount Haldane, Lord Chancellor, in Attenborough v. Solomon:
"But the question which goes to the root of this case is one which renders such a proposition wholly beside the point. If I am right, there is no question here of an executor acting in the execution of his powers, so far as this residue is concerned. The executors had long ago lost their vested right of property as executors and become, so far as the title to it was concerned, trustees under the will. Executors they remained, but they were executors who had become diverted, by their assent to the dispositions of the will, of the property which was theirs virtute officii; and their right in rem, their title of property, had been transformed into a right in personam,-a right to get the
4" (i903) i94 U. S. 6oi, 6o6. (1904) I95 U. S. 375, 382. (4 905) 197 U. S. 544, 575.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
732 YALE LAW JOURNAL
property back by proper proceedings against those in whom the property should be vested if it turned out that they required it for payment of debts for which they had made no provision."47
I9I4, Viscount Haldane, Lord Chancellor, in Sinclair v. Brougham:
"The difficulty of establishing a title in rem in this case arises from the apparent difficulty of following money. In most cases money cannot be followed. When sov- ereigns or bank notes are paid over as currency, so far as the payer is concerned, they cease ipso facto to be the subjects of specific title as chattels. If a sovereign or bank note be offered in payment it is, under ordinary cir- cumstances, no part of the duty of the person receiving it to inquire into title. The reason of this is that chattels of such a kind form part of what the law recognizes as currency, and treats as passing from hand to hand in point, not merely of possession, but of property. It would cause great inconvenience to commerce if in this class of chattel an exception were not made to the general require- ment of the law as to title.... "That seems to be, so far as the doctrine of the common law is concerned, the limit to which the exception to the rule about currency was carried; whether the case be that of a thief or of a fraudulent broker, or of money paid under mistake of fact, you can, even at law, follow, but only so long as the relation of debtor and creditor has not superseded the right in rem."48
I9I4, Lord Sumner, in Sinclair v. Brougham:
"Analogous cases have been decided with regard to chattels. They differ, no doubt, because of the fact that the property in the chattels remained unchanged, though identification and even identity of the subject-matter of the property failed, whereas here, except as to currency, and even there only in a restricted sense, the term property, as we use that term of chattels, does not apply, and, at least as far as intention could do it, both depositors and shareholders had given up the right to call the money or its proceeds their own, and had taken instead personal claims on the society."49
4 [1913] A. C. 76, 85. 8 [ 1914] A. C. 398, 4i8, 4I9. 4 [I9I4] A. C. 398, 458.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 733
i9i6, Mr. Justice Brandeis, in Kryger v. Wilson:
"If the plaintiff in error had not submitted himself to the jurisdiction of the court, the decree could have deter- mined only the title to the land, and would have left him free to assert any personal rights he may have had under the contract.""
(b) A multital right, or claim, (right in rem) is not always one relating to a thing, i. e., a tangible object: If the preceding discussion has served its various purposes, it must now be reasonably clear that the attempt to conceive of a right in rem as a right against a thing should be abandoned as intrinsically unsound, as thoroughly discredited according to good usage, and, finally, as all too likely to confuse and mislead. It is desirable, next, to emphasize, in more specific and direct form, another important point which has already been incidentally noticed: that a right in rem is not necessarily one relating to, or concerning, a thing, i. e., a tangible object. Such an assumption, although made by Leake and by many others who have given little or no attention to fundamental legal conceptions, is clearly erroneous. The term right in rem (multital right) is so generic in its denota- tion as to include: i. Multital rights, or claims, relating to a definite tangible object: e. g., a landowner's right that any ordinary person shall not enter on his land, or a chattel owner's right that any ordinary person shall not physically harm the object involved,-be it horse, watch, book, etc. 2. Multital rights (or claims) relating neither to definite tangible object nor to (tangible) person, e. g., a patentee's right, or claim, that any ordinary person shall not manufacture articles covered by the patent; 3. Multital rights, or claims, relating to the holder's own person, e. g., his right that any ordinary person shall not strike him, or that any ordinary person shall not restrain his physical liberty, i. e., "falsely imprison" him; 4. Multital rights residing in a given person and relating to another person, e. g., the right of a father that his daughter shall not be seduced, or the right of a husband that harm shall not be inflicted on his wife so as to deprive him of her company and assistance; 5. Multital rights, or claims, not relating directly to either a (tangible) person or a tangible object, e. g., a person's right that another shall not publish a libel of him, or a person's right
'? (I9x6) 37 Sup. Ct. Rep. X, 35.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
734 YALE LAW JOURNAL
that another shall not publish his picture,-the so-called "right of privacy" existing in some states, but not in all. It is thus seen that some rights in rem, or multital rights, relate fairly directly to physical objects; some fairly directly to persons; and some fairly directly neither to tangible objects nor to persons. It is, however, important to observe that there is a more specific Latin term, jus in re, which has been frequently used by able judges to indicate jural relations in rem (i. e., multital rights, privileges, powers, and immunities) directly concerning a tangible object, such as a piece of land, a vessel, etc. This form of expres- sion. appears to have been used by the classical Roman jurists almost exclusively in the more specific combination, jus in re alien (easements, profits, etc.), as contrasted with jus in re propria; but the more generic jus in re was freely employed by the modem civilians,-especially in opposition to a particular kind of jus in personal called jus ad rem.51 The following explana- tions and examples of modem usage by able judges are worthy of careful and critical consideration: i87i, Mr. Justice Markby, Elements of Law:
"It is necessary to distinguish carefully between a right in rem and a (so-called) real right. A real right is a right over a specific thing (a jus in re, as will be ex- plained hereafter). Thus a right of ownership is a real right; it is also a right in rem. But a right. to personal safety is not a real right, though it is a right in rem. "52
I9I4, Lord Dunedin, in Sinclair v. Brougham:
"The case of a chattel is easy: A shopkeeper delivers an article at the house of B. in mistake for the house of A. An action would lie against B. for restitution. Such an action could easily be founded on the right of property. To use the Roman phraseology, there would be a jus in re. And where there was a jus in re there would not be, I take
' That is, if A has a right in personam against B that the latter shall "transfer" some "legal interest," e. g., title of Blackacre, to A, A is said to have only a jus ad rem; whereas after conveyance made by B, A would have jus in re. For very interesting instances of the use of the terms jus in re and jus ad rem in connection with attempts to explain the nature of uses and trusts, see Bacon, Uses (Circa i602) Rowe's ed., pp. 5-6; Co. Lit. (i628) P. 272 b. Both of these passages are quoted in (0913) 23 YALE LAW JOURNAL, i6, notes i and 2. ' Elements of Law (6th ed., 1905) 99, note.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 735
it, any difficulty in finding a form of common law action to fit the situation. But the moment you come to deal with what in Roman phraseology is called a fungible, and especially when you deal with money, then the jus in re may disappear, and with it the appropriateness of such common law action. The familiar case is the paying of money by A. to B. under the mistaken impression in fact that a debt was due, when in truth there was no debt due. It was to fit cases of this sort that the common law evolved the action for money had and received."53
1914, Lord Kinnear, in Bank of Scotland v. Macleod:
"But to extend Lord Westbury's phrase so as to make it cover personal obligations which do not affect the real right of the obligor seems to me altogether extravagant. It was maintained in argument that every obligation with reference to any property or fund which involves a lia- bility to account fell within the principle. If that were so every imperfect security, however invalid as a real right, would be effectual as a trust."54
1855, Mr. Justice B. R. Curtis, in The Young Mechanic:
"But I will first inquire what right or interest is con- ferred by the statute, provided it intended to create such a lien, as exists by the general admiralty law upon foreign vessels. "Though the nature of admiralty liens has doubtless been long understood, it does not seem to have been described with fulness and precision, in England or this country. That it differs from what is called by the same name in the common law, is clear; for it exists inde- pendent of possession. The Bold Buccleugh, 22 Eng. L. & Eq. 62; The Nestor, I Sumn. 73. That it is not iden- tical with equitable liens, is equally clear; for the latter arise out of constructive trusts, and are neither a jus ad rem, or a jus in re; but simply a duty, binding on the conscience of the owner of the thing, and which a Court of Equity will compel him specifically to perform. 2 Story's Eq. Jurisp. ? I2I7; Ex parte Foster, 2 Story, R. 145; Clarke v. Southwick, i Curtis, 299. . . "In my opinion the definition given by Pothier of an hypothecation is an accurate description of a maritime lien under our law. 'The right which a creditor-has in a thing of another, which right consists in the power to cause that
' [1914] A. C. 398, 43I. " [1914] A. C. 3II, 324.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
736 YALE LAW JOURNAL
thing to be sold, in order to have the debt paid out of the price. This is a right in the thing, a jus in re.' TraitW de l'Hypotheque, art. prelim. See also, Sanders's Justinian, page 227. . . "Whether he can make the seizure himself, only to be followed by a judicial sale, or must resort to a court for both, may be important as to remedy, but does not affect his ultimate and essential right . . "Though tacitly created by the law, and to be executed only by the aid of a court of justice, and resulting in a judicial sale, it is as really a property in the thing as the right of a pledgee or the lien of a bailee for work. The distinction between a jus in re and a jus ad rem was familiar to lawyers of the middle ages, and is said then to have first come into practical use, as the basis of the division of rights into real and personal. Sanders' Intro. to Just. p. 49. A jus in re is a right, or property in a thing, valid as against all mankind. A jus ad rem is a valid claim on one or more persons to do something, by force of which a jus in re will be acquired. Pothier, Traite' du Droit de Domaine, ch. Pretences; Hugo, His. du Droit Rom. vol. i, p. II8. "My opinion is, that the lien conferred by the local law was an existing encumbrance on the vessel, not divested or extinguished by the death or insolvency of the owner; and that, consequently, the decree of the District Court must be affirmed."55
i90o, Mr. Chief Justice Fuller, in The Carlos F. Roses:
"The right of capture acts on the proprietary interest of the thing captured at the time of the capture and is not affected by the secret liens or private engagements of the parties. Hence the prize courts have rejected in its favor the lien of bottomry bonds, of mortgages, for supplies, and of bills of lading. The assignment of bills of lading transfers the jus ad rem, but not necessarily the jus in rem. The jus in re or in rem implies the absolute dominion,- the ownership independently of any particular relation with another person. The jus ad rem has for its founda- tion an obligation incurred by another. Sand. Inst. Just. Introd., xlviii; 2 Marcade, Expl. du Code Napoleon, 350; 2 Bouvier, (Rawle's Revision), 73; The Young Mechanic, 2 Curtis, 404. "Claimants did not obtain the jus in rem, and, according to the great weight of authority, the right of capture was superior." 6
X (I85j) 2 Curtis, 404, 406, 410, 411, 412, 414. 5" (I900) 177 U. S. 655, 666.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 737
i870, Mr. Justice Foster, in Jacobs v. Knapp:
"That statute provides that 'any person who labors at cutting, hauling, or drawing wood, bark, logs, or lumber, shall have a lien thereon for his personal services, which lien shall take precedence of all other claims except liens on account of public taxes, to continue sixty days after the services are performed, and may be secured by attachment.' "At the common law the lien of a mechanic, manufac- turer, or other laborer 'is neither a jus ad rem nor a jus in re: that is to say, it is not a right of property in the thing itself, or a right of action to the thing itself;' but it is a security, derived from a 'general principle of the common law, which gives to a man who has the lawful possession of a thing and has expended his money or his labor upon it, at the request of the owner, a right to retain it until his demand is satisfied.' "A lien, as we have seen, is a personal right, as well as an interest which can only be created by the owner, or by his authority. If Fifield, by virtue of his contract with the defendants, had a lien upon the wood, the plaintiff could acquire no lien upon the property through him. The plaintiff, as a creditor of Fifield, could not attach and hold, as against the owner, at the common law, the prop- erty in which Fifield had but the qualified interest of a pledgee. Lovett v. Brown, 40 N. H. 5Ii. Neither is a lien for the price of labor performed on an article assign- able. Bradley v. Spofford, 23 N. H. 447. "The statutes of liens have enlarged the privileges of the party who, at common law, could only as bailee avail himself of the lien, by substituting, in the enumerated cases, attachment of the property for retention of posses- sion; but it would be quite anomalous to regard this process of attachment as applying in favor of a stranger against a party with whom the plaintiff never contracted, and who could in no proper sense be regarded as an attaching creditor. . . ."57
The passage from Mr. Justice Foster-the last of the above quotations-seems open to comment. If at common law the lien of the mechanic, manufacturer or other laborer consists of the "right to retain" the "thing" in his possession or, to use Mr. Justice Foster's own later and more discriminating term, a "privilege" of retaining possession, this is certainly a "privi- lege" relating to a "thing." More than that, such privileges are multilal privileges, or privileges in rem, existing not only
It (i870) 50 N. H. 71, 75.
54
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
738 YALE LAW JOURNAL
against the owner of the chattel but also against all persons in general, and correlating with no-rights in the latter. These multital privileges relate directly to the physical "thing"; and they are "rights" in the very broad sense of that term. It is difficult, therefore, to see why the term jus in re should not be applicable. For the latter term does not seem to be confined to rights in the sense of claims, this being shown by the above- quoted opinion of Mr. Justice Curtis, whose characterization of common-law liens differs from that of Mr. Justice Foster. It is also clear that the lienor has, by virtue of his possession per se, rights in rem against all others that they shall not disturb that possession or harm the -object possessed. These last are rights or claims literally relating to the thing; and, therefore, so far at least as the literal meaning of jus in re is concerned there seems to be no reason why the latter expression should not be applied. It is true that if the lienor were to surrender possession he would thereby divest himself of his privilege (against the owner) and his rights, or claims, against the owner and others; but while those relations exist they concern the thing, and that fact is obviously not negatived by the possibility of their being divested. The passage last quoted from Mr. Justice Markby and also the extracts from the opinions of Lord Kinnear and Mr. Justice Curtis show that those rights in rem which directly relate to things-land, vessels, etc.-instead of being called jus in re are, occasionally denominated "real"-a term meaning literally, of course, "relating to a thing." "Real rights" in this sense are opposed to rights in personal relating to things. Thus, e. g., if A is owner of a horse, he has jus in re or "real rights"; if, on the other hand, X is under contract to transfer the ownership of a horse to A, the latter has that sort of right in personam which would sometimes be called jus ad rem, or "personal right." In the restricted sense now referred to, it seems clear that real rights as a class also exclude both rights in personam and rights in rem that do not relate directly to things, or tangible objects. The following passages may be considered with advantage: 19I4, Professor E. C. Clark, History of Roman Lacw: Juris- prudence:
"Jura realia and personalia are expressions occasionally used by modern civilians as adjectival forms for jura in rem and in personal, but only as confined to Property Law. (E. G., the translator of Mackeldey, Pr. ii. ? I5.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 739
Austin (T. and N. ii. 5, pp. 977, 978; St. Note on Lect. I4, p. i84) identifies the pairs without the above qualifi- cation.) This at least seems to be the meaning given by Savigny to jura realia, if represented by the correspond- ing German dingliche Rechte. (System, i, ? 56, p. 369. Alle mogliche Rechte an Sachen . ... fassen wir unter dem gemeinsamen Namen der dinglichen Rechte zusammen.) ",58
I855, Mr. Justice B. R. Curtis, in The Young Mechanic:
"The distinction between a jus in re and a jus ad rem was familiar to lawyers of the middle ages, and is said then to have first come into practical use, as the basis of the division of rights into real and personal. Sanders' Intro. to Just. p. 49. A jus in re is a right, or property in a thing, valid as against all mankind. A jus ad rem is a valid claim on one or more persons to do something, by force of which a jus in re will be acquired. Pothier, Traiti du Droit de Domaine, ch. Pretences; Hugo, His. du Droit Rom. vol. i, p. II8. 59
I9I4, Lord Kinnear, in Bank of Scotland v. Macleod:
"But to extend Lord Westbury's phrase so as to make it cover personal obligations which do not affect the real right of the obligor seems to me altogether extravagant. It was maintained in argument that every obligation with reference to any property or fund which involves a lia- bility to account fell within the principle. If that were so every imperfect security, however invalid as a real right, would be effectual as a trust."60
Even when restricted as above indicated, the pair of terms, "real" and "personal," seems an undesirable one for English- speaking lawyers and judges because those words are already definitely appropriated to different and independent classifications and are constantly applied in connection with the latter. Thus, e. g., we have "real property" and "personal property"; and this classification is obviously not parallel with that of "real rights" and "personal rights"-both of the latter terms being applicable either to "personal property" relations or to "real property" relations. Then too, the expression "personal rights" is espe-
"8History of Roman Law: Jurisprudence (1914) Vol. II, p. 7i8. 6 (i855) 2 Curtis, 404, 412. ' [1914] A. C. 3II, 324.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
740 YALE LAW JOURNAL
cially misleading in its connotation because, literally, it tends to suggest rights concerning a person as the object to which the rights relate, that is, either the person who holds the rights or some other person. It is therefore most fortunate that the pair of terms, "'real rights" and "personal rights," is not at all com- mon in judicial opinions or in legal treatises. Over against this, however, it must be recognized that courts not infrequently use a somewhat similar pair of terms, viz., the expression "'personal rights" or "personal claims" in opposition to some such expres- sion as "property rights," "title to land," "interest in the thing," etc."' Finally, as regards this particular matter, it must be regretted that some authors, though no courts whatever so far as has been observed, use the terms "real rights" and "personal rights" as exact equivalents, respectively, for all kinds of rights in rem (whether relating directly to things or persons or to neither) and all kinds of rights in personal. It is greatly to be hoped that such an unusual and, for the English law, misleading use of terms will not become at all common. (c) A single multital right, or claim, (right in rem) correlates with a duty resting on one person alone, not with many duties- (or one duty) resting upon all the members of a very large and indefinite class of persons: Though fairly implicated with what has been said in the "preliminary" explanation of ideas and terms,62 this proposition now requires more detailed considera- tion; for it represents a considerable departure from the explana- tions or analyses to be found in treatises on jurisprudence or in books on particular branches of the law. Let us first have definitely before us some typical passages: i832, Professor John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence, or the Philosophy of Positive Law:
"All rights reside in persons, and are rights to acts or forbearances on the part of other persons.... "The essentials of a right in rem are these: "It resides in a determinate person, or in determinate persons, and avails against other persons universally or
'See the quotations given ante: Mr. Justice Holmes, pp. 730-731 ; Mr. Justice Brandeis, p. 733; Lord Sumner, p. 732. See also the term "personal rights" as used by Mr. Justice Holmes, dissenting, in the very recent case of Southern Pacific Co. v. Jensen (U. S. Sup. Ct., May 21, 1917). ' See ante, pp. 718 ff.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 741
generally. Further, the duty with which it correlates, or to which it corresponds, is negative: that is to say, a duty to forbear or abstain. "The duty which correlates with [a right in remi attaches upon persons generally."63
i87I, Mr. Justice Markby, Elements of Law:
"The persons to whom a right in rem belongs may be changed to any extent within the limits allowed by the law, but the persons upon whom the duty corresponding to a right in rem is imposed cannot be changed, because all persons are under that duty."04
i88o, Professor Thomas Erskine Holland, Elements of Juris- prudence:
"'A right is available either against a definite person or persons, or against all persons indefinitely.... "This distinction between rights has been expressed by calling a right of the definite kind a right in personal, of the indefinite kind a right in rem."65
I902, Mr. Solicitor-General Salmond, Jurisprudence:
"A real right corresponds to a duty imposed on persons in general. . . . The indeterminate incidence of the duty which corresponds to a real right, renders impossible many modes of dealing with it which are of importance in the case of personal rights."06
I9I5, Professor Harlan Fiske Stone, Law and its Adminis- tration:
"One may have a right against all members of the com- munity indifferently. Thus one has the right not to have his person or his property unlawfully interfered with, and this right exists generally against all members of the community."87
i9i6, Professor Samuel Williston, Is the Right of an Assignee of a Chose in Action Legal or Equitable.?
Jurisp. (5th ed., i885) Vol. I, pp. 368, 394, 371, 586. 'Elements of Law (6th ed., 1905) pp. 91, 99. '%Jurisp. (ioth ed., igo6) p. 139. Jurisp. (4th ed., 1913) pp. 202, 203. e7Law and its Administration (1915) p. 53.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
742 YALE LAW JOURNAL
"Though legal ownership is conceived fundamentally as a right good against all the world, actual instances of such ownership are often much more narrowly limited. The owner of a chattel which has been stolen from him is likely to find his right against the world considerably qualified if the thief is in a place where the principles of market overt prevail."68
In opposition to the ideas embodied in the passages just given,69 it is submitted that instead of there being a single right with a single correlative duty resting on all the persons against whom the right avails, there are many separate and distinct rights, actual and potential, each one of which has a correlative duty resting upon some one person. Repeating a hypothetical case put above, let us suppose that A is the owner of Blackacre and X is the owner of Whiteacre. It may be assumed further that, in consideration of $ioo actually paid by A to B, the latter agrees with A never to enter on X's land, Whiteacre; also that C and D, at the 'same time and for separate considerations, make respective similar agreements with A. In such a case A's respective rights against B, C, and D are clearly rights in personaam, or paucital rights. Surely no one would assert that A has only a single right against B, C, and D, with only a single or unified duty resting on the latter. A's right against B is entirely separate from the other two. B may commit a breach of his duty, without involving any breach of C's duty by C or any breach of D's duty by D. For, obviously, the content of each respective duty differs from each of the others. To make it otherwise C and D would have to be under a duty or duties (along with B) that B should not enter on X's land. Even if that were the case, there would be said to be three separate duties unless B, C, and D bound them- selves so as to create a so-called joint obligation. In the latter case alone would there be said to be a single right and a single (joint) duty. Going beyond this direct analysis of the situation, it seems clear that the three respective "right-duty" relations of A and B, A and C, and A and D respond to every test of separateness and independence. A might discharge B from his duty to A, thus (in equivalent terms) creating a privilege of entering as against A (not- as against X, of course); yet,
(i9i6) 30 HARV. L. REV. 97, 98. ' See also the various judicial opinions from which quotations are given ante pp. 729-733.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 743
obviously, the respective duties of C and D would continue the same as before. Point for point, the same considerations and tests seem applicable to A's respective rights in rem, or multital rights, against B, C, D, and others indefinitely that they, respectively considered, shall not enter on Blackacre. It is not a case of one joint duty of the same content resting on all-e. g., that B should not enter on Blackacre.70 Consistently with this view, A might, e. g., extinguish B's duty or, in other words, grant B the privilege of entering by giving "leave and license" to do so. In such event, of course, the respective duties of C, D, E, and all others would continue to exist, precisely as before. In order to see even more clearly that the supposed single right in rem correlating with "a duty" on "all" persons really involves as many separate and distinct "right-duty" relations as there are persons subject to a duty, it may be worth while to reverse the situation somewhat, and consider, in anticipation of a more general treatment at a later point, the subject of duties in rem, or multital duties. Thus, e. g., X is under duty not to strike R,
70 Compare, however, special cases like Thorpe v. Brumfitt (i873) L. R. 8 Ch. App. 65o, involving a suit for an injunction against several defendants for disturbance of plaintiff's right of way. Lord Justice James said: "The plaintiff cannot complain, unless he can prove an obstruction which injures him. The case is not like one of trespass, which gives a right of action though no damage be proved. In the present case, I cannot come to any other conclusion than that arrived at by the Master of the Rolls, that the right of access to the inn-yard has been interfered with in a way most prejudicial to the Plaintiff. Nothing can be much more injurious to the owner of an inn than that the way to his yard should be constantly obstructed by the loading and unloading of heavy waggons. If a person who was going to put up his horses at the inn was stopped by the loading or unloading of waggons, he would probably at once go to another inn. Then it was said that the Plaintiff alleges an obstruction caused by several persons acting independently of each other, and does not shew what share each had in causing it. It is probably impossible for a person in the Plaintiff's position to shew this. Nor do I think it necessary that he should shew it. The amount of obstruction caused by any one of them might not, if it stood alone, be sufficient to give any ground of complaint, though the amount caused by them all may be a serious injury. Suppose one person leaves a wheelbarrow standing on a way, that may cause no appreciable inconvenience, but if a hundred do so, that may cause a serious inconvenience, which a person entitled to the use of the way has a right to prevent; and it is no defence to any one person among the hundred to say that what he does causes of itself no damage to the complainant."
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
744 YALE LAW JOURNAL
S, T, or any other ordinary member of the community. Are we to say that, as regards these many persons, X has but a single duty,"' and that, correlatively, there is but a single right held by R, S, T, and all the others? Manifestly not, for each one of these persons has a distinct and independent right; and any one of such independent rights might cease to exist without in the least affecting the others. If, e. g., R threatens bodily harm to X, R's right that X shall not strike him becomes thereby extinguished, and a no-right in R substituted; or, correlatively, in such contingency, X's duty to R ceases, and X acquires a privilege of self-defense against R. But such change in no way affects the entirely distinct relations existing between X and the various other persons involved. As regards the separateness and relativity of all "right-duty" relations, the following judicial reasoning seems accurate and persuasive:
i908, Mr. Justice Connor, in McGhee v. R. Co.:
"It is elementary that plaintiff had no cause of action against defendants for placing the dynamite in the shanty. He must establish some relation between defendants and himself from which a duty to him is imposed upon defen- dants. 'The expression "duty" properly imports a deter- minate person to whom the obligation is owing, as well as the one who owes the obligation. There must be two determinate parties before the relationship of obligor and obligee of a duty can exist.' "172
With this passage we may well compare the instructive opinion of an eminent English judge emphasizing the distinct and relative character of each "privilege-no-right" relation connected with a given matter, his observations being equally applicable to "right-duty" relations:
I906, Lord Collins, M. R., in Thomas v. Bradbury, Agnew, & Co., Ltd.:
7' Some would say yes: compare Sir Frederick Pollock, Jurisprudence (2d ed., i9o4) 64: "Doubtless there are duties without any determinate rights corresponding to them: indeed, this is the case, in any view, with the negative duties which we owe to the community at large. For my duty not to damage other people's goods, for example, is one duty, not millions of separate duties owed to every one who has anything to be damaged, or in respect of every separate chattel of any value." n (igo8) i47 N. C. i42, i46.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FUNDAMENTAL LEGAL CONCEPTIONS 745
"The right" [privilege] "of fair comment, though shared by the public, is the right" [privilege] "of every individual who asserts it, and is, qua him, an individual right whatever name it be called by, and comment by him which is coloured by malice cannot from his standpoint be deemed fair. He, and he only, is the person in whose motives the plaintiff in the libel action is concerned, and if he, the person sued, is proved to have allowed his view to be distorted by malice, it is quite immaterial that some- body else might without malice have written an equally damnatory criticism. The defendant, and not that other person, is the party sued."73
If, then, the foregoing line of reasoning be sound, the following points would seem to be reasonably clear: A right in rem, or multital right, correctly understood, is simply one of a large number of fundamentally similar rights residing in one person; and any one of such rights has as its correlative one, and only one, of a large number of general, or common, duties,-that is, fundamentaly similar duties residing respectively in many dif- ferent persons. Similarly, a duty in rem, or multital duty, is one of a large number of fundamentally similar duties residing in one person; and any one of such duties has as its correlative one of a large number of general, or common, rights, or claims,-that is, fundamentally similar rights, or claims, residing respectively in many different persons. It is therefore to be hoped that, instead of continuing to be used to indicate the entire multi- plicity of separate and independent rights, or claims, that a person may have against many others, the term right in rem may gradually come to be used to represent one, and only one, of this multiplicity of distinct rights. Whatever be the fate of the con- cept and term, right in rem, in this regard, it is surely of the utmost importance that the various possible analyses and mean- ings involved be carefully pondered and understood; and, in the meanwhile, the term "multital"-free as it is from any previous hazy connotations-will without question serve definitely to indi- cate one, and one only, of such a multiplicity of rights as is now under consideration. (d) A multital right, or claim, (right in rem) should not be confused with any co-existing privileges or other jural relations that the holder of the multital right or rights may have in respect to the same subject-matter: As already incidentally noticed, it is
I [i906] 2 K. B. 627, 638.
This content downloaded from 130.132.173.108 on Thu, 30 May 2013 17:35:06 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
746 YALE LAW JOURNAL
feared that the exact nature of multital rights has been greatly obscured not only by the habitual tendency to treat a multiplicity of fundamentally similar rights, or claims, as if they were only one, but also by the equally strong tendency to include under the hazy blanket term, right in rem, especially in the case of tangible objects, the multiplicity of privileges and other jural relations that the holder of the multital right or rights may have. Suppose, for example, that A is fee-simple owner of Blackacre. His "legal interest" or "property" relating to the tangible object that we call land consists of a complex aggregate of rights (or claims), privileges, powers, and immunities.74 First: A has multital legal rights, or claims, that others, respectively, shall not enter on the land, that they shall not cause physical harm to the land, etc., such others being under respective correlative legal duties. Second: A has an indefinite number of legal privileges of entering on the land, using the land, harming the land, etc., that is, within limits fixed by law on grounds of social and economic policy, he has privileges of doing on or to the land what he pleases; and correlative to all such legal privileges are the respective legal no-rights of other persons. Third: A has the legal power to alienate his legal interest to another, i. e., to extinguish his complex aggregate of jural relations and create a new and similar aggregate in the other person; also the legal power to create a life estate in another and concurrently to create a reversion in himself; also the legal power to create a privilege of entrance in any other person by giving "leave and license"; and so on indefinitely. Correlative to all such legal powers are the legal liabilities in other persons,-this meaning that the latter are subject, nolens volens, to the changes of jural relations involved in the exercise of A's powers. Fourth: A has an indefinite number of legal immunities, using the term immunity in the very specific sense of non-liability or non-subjection to a power on the part of another person. Thus he has the im- munity that no ordinary person can alienate A's legal interest or aggregate of jural relations to another person; the immunity