Main menu
Harm
by Roger Shiner
The Problem
A legal system performs many social functions (see, for example (Raz 1979, Chapter 9). Prominent among such functions is the promotion of the welfare and security of citizens and their property. H.L.A. Hart famously distinguished between laws that impose duties by which citizens must abide, and laws that provide facilities that citizens can make use of if they wish (Hart 1994, 27–9). The promotion of welfare and security involves both kinds of law. Criminal law directly imposes duties of action and restraint, as does the law of tort or delict. Contract law, for example, provides for the enforcement of agreements made but not kept. This function at the highest level of generality may be characterized as the use of law to prevent, or to provide compensation for, harm. `Harm’ may be characterized at this level of generality as `the thwarting, setting back, or defeating of an interest’ (Feinberg 1984, 33).
The law’s exercise of this harm-
However, it is intuitively clear that the matter cannot be so straightforward, if we substitute for `harm’ in the Principle a broad characterization such as `setback to interests’. If A runs over B’s pet rat with his car, B suffers a setback to her interests, but it is not clear that causing B this loss should as such be subject to coercive penalty: further questions remain as to how or in what state of mind such harm was caused. Moreover, many legal systems make simply the possession of small amounts of marijuana a criminal offence; yet it is not clear how simply the possession in itself of a small amount of marijuana constitutes a harm, as opposed, for example, to its dissemination or consumption. Even if the Harm Principle validly comprehends regulation of behaviour likely to result in harm, there are still many questions as to the proper degree of likelihood, for example. If the Harm Principle is a guide to the proper way for the law to exercise its harm-
Discussion
As Feinberg pointed out (Feinberg 1984, 31), the basic core of the notion of `harm’, insofar as it is of interest to the law, seems to be that of a `harmed condition’; someone is in the condition of being harmed: a setback to interests has occurred. But clearly there are `harms’ so understood in which the law’s interest will rapidly vanish. A person whose heart failure results from the natural course of disease is in the same harmed condition (in this sense of `harmed condition’) as one whose heart failure results from the ingestion of deliberately administered poison. This point leads to the thought that the notion required for jurisprudential purposes is not so much `harm’ as `wrong’ or unjustified violation of right. Not all harms are wrongs (suppose I put the poison into your drink by accident). So the focus has to be on that subset of harms that are also wrongs.
What, however, is it that turns a harm into a wrong? What do we need to add, to define the relevant subset? Obviously, one element is causation: one important difference between the rock hitting you as a result of a landslide and the rock hitting you as a result of my throwing it lies in the cause of the rock hitting you. But more is needed. Consider the difference between my throwing the rock and you unforeseeably getting into its path, my throwing the rock without paying any attention to who might get hit, and my throwing it intending to hit you. The law’s interest in your `harmed condition’ of being rock-
This train of thought leads to what has been called by Duff the `conduct-
Scope: Concerns about the scope of the model, even in the case of those who fundamentally accept the model as valid, fall into four chief classes.
i) Moral harm (see also LEGAL MORALISM): on occasion the law has tried to control coercively action that damages, not citizens’ bodies or property, but (as it were) their souls. Laws regulating pornography, for example, have often been phrased in terms of `a tendency to deprave and corrupt’: the underlying though is that harm is done by the dissemination of pornography, harm to those who are exposed to it. The harm is not physical, but moral: those exposed will become worse persons. The liberty-
ii) Offence: People take offence at many things, and, subjectively at least, the resulting feelings constitute a `harm’, a `setback to interests’. But should we allow the causation of such feelings to invoke the coercive power of the law? Again, the standard liberal approach is to take the Harm Principle as not including `harm’ in the sense of `offence’. Feinberg usefully distinguishes between `bare-
iii) Paternalism: Mill in his original presentation of the statement that became known as the Harm Principle also explicitly ruled out paternalism. The passage quoted above continues: `His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant’ — warrant to exercise power over him against his will, that is. But the issue is not so simple, especially in the case of legal paternalism (see Husak 2003). One difficulty is even in plausibly identifying legislation as paternalistic: much supposedly paternalistic legislation is defensible as promoting citizen and community welfare. Moreover, justifications for paternalism exist, especially what might be called autonomy-
iv) Inchoate offences: All legal systems proscribe, not merely the bringing about of harmful results, but also activities that stand in relations of various sorts to such results without bringing them about. It is against the law, for example, to attempt to murder, as well as to murder; to conspire to defraud, as well as to defraud; to risk injury, as well as to cause injury. It does not seem difficult to find ways of justifying such offences, because of their connection to the bringing about of harmful results and the culpability implicit in such a connection (on attempts, for example, see Duff 1996). Nonetheless, the Harm Principle is here being interpreted, not simply applied.
The `Conduct-
This point can, second, be extended more widely. Consider again the Canadian definition of sexual assault, invoking the idea of `circumstances of a sexual nature’. This reference to `circumstances of a sexual nature’ brings out that the whole matter of the occurrence of harm so as to concern the law is fundamentally social in character. The harm-
Conclusion. These are large and complex issues, and are not settled here. But this much is clear. Within the liberal democratic tradition, the concept of harm can have a valid use at a high level of generality and abstraction to gesture towards a large area of the law’s concern with the control of human action. To encapsulate this concern in the Harm Principle is permissible. But to do that is not the same as using the Harm Principle mechanically as a concrete guide to the design of the law. It is much too inexact for that. If one is coming from a long way outside the liberal democratic tradition, then to arrive at the point where the Harm Principle seems to get everything right is hard, but worthwhile, work. However, within the liberal democratic tradition, to arrive at the Harm Principle is easy. The hard work lies ahead.
References
Duff, R. 1990. Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability: Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law. Oxford: Blackwell.
Duff, R. 1996. Criminal Attempts. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Duff, R. 2001. `Harms and Wrongs’. Buffalo Criminal Law Review 5:13–45.
Duff, R. 2002. `Rule-
Feinberg, J. 1984. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law. Vol. I, Harm to Others. New York: Oxford University Press.
Feinberg, J. 1985. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law. Vol. II, Offense to Others. New York: Oxford University Press.
Feinberg, J. 1988. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law. Vol. IV, Harmless Wrongdoing. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hart, H. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd edn. Ed. P. A. Bulloch and J. Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Husak, D. 2003. `Legal Paternalism’. In Oxford Handbook to Practical Ethics, ed. H. LaFollette, 387–412. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Mill, J. S. 1977. On Liberty. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. 18. Ed. J. M. Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Shiner, R. A. 1986. `Pornography and Freedom of Speech’. In Freedom of Speech: Basis and Limits, ed. G. Maher. Archiv für Rechts-
Sumner, L. 2004. The Hateful and the Obscene: Studies in the Limits of Free Expression. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.